Научная статья на тему 'ARIST. POET. 1454A31-33 AGAIN'

ARIST. POET. 1454A31-33 AGAIN Текст научной статьи по специальности «Языкознание и литературоведение»

CC BY
21
4
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
Журнал
Philologia Classica
Scopus
ВАК
Ключевые слова
ARISTOTELES / POETICS / EURIPIDES / IPHIGENIA IN AULIS / THE CONCEPT OF HOMALON

Аннотация научной статьи по языкознанию и литературоведению, автор научной работы — Kostyleva Tatiana V.

Among the examples on how not to portray a character in tragedy, Aristotle names the female protagonist of the Iphigenia in Aulis, claiming that she is drawn in violation of the principle of consistency: begging to spare her life she is much unlike her later self. Philologists stood for Euripides, charging Aristotle with a lack of intuitive understanding. Moreover, as has been pointed out, the unaffected character of Iphigenia’s behaviour could find a footing in the ample observations on human psychology Aristotle himself made elsewhere in the Ethics and Rhethoric. Certain modern scholars, however, tend to side with Aristotle. To argumentatively prove or disprove the feasibility of the change Iphigenia undergoes seems thus to be close to impossible, both psychologically and aesthetically. A thought not alien to the Poetics goes as simple as that: not all the shifts and turns, so human and so easily observed in life, should find their way into art. One supposes Aristotle all too well recognised the fact that no example would in this case prove to be free of blame, while holding that the general applicability and inherent veracity of his theory goes unimpaired by the fact that it could in principle be assailed.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.

Текст научной работы на тему «ARIST. POET. 1454A31-33 AGAIN»

iehihhih

MISCELLANEA

HIUUUH

philologia classica

vol. 15. fasc. 2. 2020

UDC 821.14

Arist. Poet. 1454a31-33 Again*

Tatiana V. Kostyleva

St. Petersburg State University,

7-9, Universitetskaya nab., St. Petersburg, 199034, Russian Federation; t.kostyleva@spbu.ru National Research University "Higher School of Economics",

123, nab. Kanala Griboedova, St. Petersburg, 190068, Russian Federation; tkostyleva@hse.ru

For citation: Kostyleva T. V. Arist. Poet. 1454a31-33 Again. Philologia Classica 2020, 15 (2), 411-415. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu20.2020.214

Among the examples on how not to portray a character in tragedy, Aristotle names the female protagonist of the Iphigenia in Aulis, claiming that she is drawn in violation of the principle of consistency: begging to spare her life she is much unlike her later self. Philologists stood for Euripides, charging Aristotle with a lack of intuitive understanding. Moreover, as has been pointed out, the unaffected character of Iphigenia's behaviour could find a footing in the ample observations on human psychology Aristotle himself made elsewhere in the Ethics and Rheth-oric. Certain modern scholars, however, tend to side with Aristotle. To argumentatively prove or disprove the feasibility of the change Iphigenia undergoes seems thus to be close to impossible, both psychologically and aesthetically. A thought not alien to the Poetics goes as simple as that: not all the shifts and turns, so human and so easily observed in life, should find their way into art. One supposes Aristotle all too well recognised the fact that no example would in this case prove to be free of blame, while holding that the general applicability and inherent veracity of his theory goes unimpaired by the fact that it could in principle be assailed. Keywords: Aristoteles, Poetics, Euripides, Iphigenia in Aulis, the concept of homalon.

In chapter fifteen of the Poetics, which leaves an impression of being rather fragmentary, Aristotle drops in passing several remarks on the importance of character in its own right within the tragic plot and prescribes four requirements which a poet is advised to strive to meet should he wish to evoke the inherently tragic feelings of pity and fear. By way of a hallmark explanation, some negative examples are given. It is the one for 'consistency', the fourth requirement, that does prompt some locking of horns on part of Aristotle's readership and, by nature of the example, Euripides scholarship. Reluctant as one is, there is no denying the fact that this example from Iphigenia in Aulis has drawn

* This article is part of the project "Thesaurus criticus to Aristotle's Poetics" supported by the Russian Science Foundation (Project Nr. 18-18-0060).

© St. Petersburg State University, 2020

a disproportionate amount of attention due to it being one of the relatively few1 in the Poetics to come from an extant tragedy of which we have considerable knowledge, albeit the posthumously (405 BC) staged draft still encourages reconstructions of varying merit.2

tstaptov 5s то 6|aA6v. Kav Y&p avw|aA6c ti; r| 6 t^v |i|r|aiv naps^wv Ka! toioutov r|9oc unotsGfl, ö|w; ö^aÄü; ävw|aAov 5ä etvai. sativ 5s napa5siY|a nov^pta; |sv ^9ou; цг| ävaYKata; olov ö MsvsXao; ö ¿v тф 'Opsatri, tou 5s änpsnoü; Ka! ц^ äp^öttovtoc ö t£ 9p^vo; O5uaasw; ¿v tfl 2киХХг| Ka! ^ t^c MsXavinnr|C p^ai;, tou 5s ävw|aXou ^ ¿v AüXi5i 'IfrysvEia- oü5sv Y&p soiKsv ^ [Kstsuouaa tfl üatspa.3

"And the fourth is consistency; for even if the person being imitated is an inconsistent sort, and that kind of character has been posited, still he should be consistently inconsistent. A case of baseness of character not required by any necessity, is, for example, Menelaus in the Orestes; of unsuitability and inappropriateness, the lamentation of Odysseus in the Scylla and the speech of Melanippe, and of inconsistency — the Iphigenia in Aulis; for the suppliant has no resemblance to the later one."4

The sheer volume of scholarly output these much-thought-about and thought-into lines have prompted testifies to the thrill every student of ancient drama feels when an opportunity to challenge (or defend) the philosopher's idea lies, seemingly, within reach. U. von Wilamowitz, an early champion of Euripides, expressed in 1889 his bewilderment and discontent that Aristotle "so gröblich sich versehen kann, die aulische Iphigenie zu tadeln, weil sie nicht entweder lediglich als schlachtopfer weint, oder als heldenjungfrau mutvolle reden hält."5 J. Markland well before that observed that we should rather praise Euripides for the fact that he "humani animi levitatem, et то e^eTäßArfTOv, et inconstan-tiam in consiliis suis per tot instabiles dramatis personas repraesentaret",6 thus represent-

1 See Schoder 1969, 75 for a list of literary sources cited in the Poetics; to take Euripides only, Aristotle cites three extant plays (IT, IA, Medea), two lost (Chresphontes, Melanippe), and one unknown; other instances refer to his work in general.

2 See Günther 1988, Diggle 1994, with Mastronarde 1996-1997, 201-202; Kovacs 1998, 270-272; 2003, 77-103.

3 The text follows Taran 2012 here reproducing Kassel 1965. The the ms variants and editor's emendations, though curious per se, are mostly irrelevant for the present discussion. The established text is sound. Vettori supposes that before tou 5s dvw|a\ou an example of dvo|ioiov was given, but Aristoteles was not obliged to exemplify all of his critical judgements.

4 Translation adopted from Else 1957, 455 with minor alterations to it. A. Schmitt 2008, 21 is adequate and clear: "Das Vierte ist, dass der Charakter konsistent sein soll. Denn auch wenn der, der das Vorbild für die Nachahmung bietet, sich selbst nicht treu bleibt, und ein solcher Charakter Gegenstand der Nachahmung ist, muss das Ungleichmäßige als dessen charakterliche Konstante dargestellt werden. Ein Beispiel für einen Charakter, der ohne Not als verdorben dargestellt wird, ist die Zeichnung des Menelaos im Orest. Ein Beispiel für ein Verhalten, das zu einem Charakter nicht passt und ihm nicht angemessen ist, gibt die Klage-Arie [threnos] des Odysseus in der Skylla und die Rede [rhesis] der Melanippe. Ein Beispiel für eine Charakterzeichnung, der es an Konstanz mangelt, bietet die Iphigenie in Aulis. Denn die flehentlich bittende Iphigenie hat keinerlei Ähnlichkeit mit der Iphigenie im späteren Verlauf des Stücks". Bywater 1909, 43, who reads ünoti9dc in 1454a27, translates "even if inconsistency be part of the man before one for imitation as presenting that form of character", which is verbose and complicated in the middle due to the participle. Something like 'even if the original character ('in the myth', thus Lucas 1968, 160) is inconsistent and such a character is intended for representation (not, as Lucas, ibid., 'supplied' by the myth), they should be consistently inconsistent' could be offered as an alternative.

5 Wilamowitz 1906, 115 (an introduction to his Heracles turned into the introduction).

6 Markland 1811, 95, ad v. 1375.

ing to avw^aXov o^aXwc;. Aristotle scholars are careful to suppose that the philosopher had his own subjective reasons for such criticism, or pass over this passage in silence.7

Argumentative defenses of the tragedian, quite surprisingly, can go along the lines of Aristotelian moral philosophy, with scholars looking for proofs of Iphigenia's 'constancy,' 'a being-equal-to-oneself' in the Nicomachean (1168b) and Eudemian (1240a) Ethics. Thus, M. McDonald offers grounds for Iphigenia's consistency in her fiXia: a "reverent and dutiful daughter," Iphigenia "listens well," "respects her father's lesson" and, seeing that "it is not her character that has changed, but her circumstances and her reaction to them", she "acts naturally and nobly when she makes her final choice ... and acquires immortal fame in the process".8 Indeed, there is little real action in this play populated with men pressed hard by circumstances in which they shift and turn, a welcome foil for a heroic act of resolution. It thus remains largely unexplained why Aristotle himself failed to interpret and justify Iphigenia's behaviour in terms of his own moral philosophy which McDonald so admirably wields against him. The 1990s saw what seems a considerable surge in interest in this play and Iphigenia's character in particular: W. Stockert in his commentary relies on the passage in the Rhetoric 1389a, where Aristotle observes a specific propensity of the young and inexperienced to impulsive, heroic deeds.9 Cf. Rhet. 1389a-b:

o[ [i£v ouv vsoi Ta slalv smGu^r|TiKoi, Kal oioi noistv wv av smGu^awai. <...> su^sTa-PoXoi 5s Kal oytKopoi npo; Ta; smGu^lac;, Kal afo5pa ^sv smGu^ouai Taxsw; 5s nauovTai (o^stai Yap a[ ^ouX^asi; Kal ou ^sYaXai, wansp a[ twv Ka^vovTwv Styai Kal nstvai), Kal Gu-^iKol Kal o^uGu^oi Kal oloi aKoXouGstv Tfl opYfl. Kal ^ttou; slal Tou Gu^ou 5ia Yap fiXoTi^l-av ouk avs^ovTai oXiYwpou^svoi, aXX' aYavaKTouaiv av o'iwvTai a5iKstaGai. Kal fiXoTi^oi ^sv slaiv, ^aXXov 5s fiXoviKoi (unspox^c Yap smGu^st ^ vsoT^C, ^ 5s vi.Kr| unspox^ Tic;), <...> Kal avSpsioTspoi (Gu^wSsi; Yap Kal susXniSs;, wv to ^sv ^ fo^staGai to 5s Gappstv noist <...> Kal ^sYaXo^uxoi (ou Yap uno tou piou nw TsTansivwvTai, aXXa twv avaYKaiwv ansipoi slaiv, Kal to a^iouv auTov ^sYaXwv ^YaXo^uxta^ touto 5' susXni5o;).

"The young are eager by character and can readily do whatever they desire; <...> changeable and quickly tiring of their desires, they desire keenly, but soon cool down (for their desires are keen, but not strong, much like the thirst and hunger of the sick), they are passionate and irascible, and given to fits of strong emotion, unable to control them; being ambitious, they cannot bear to be slighted, and become indignant every time they think themselves wronged. They seek honours, being especially fond of victories (for youth desires superiority, and a victory is some kind of superiority) <...> And they are more brave (for they are spirited and hopeful, the former makes them not afraid, the latter stirs them to courage) <.> They are high-minded (life has not yet humbled them, nor the virtue of necessity made

7 Bywater 1909, 229 tacitly refers the reader to lines ll. 1211-1212 and 1368-1369. of the play; Lucas 1968, 161: "such changes are rare in Greek tragedy; that of Neoptolemus in the Phil. is one with which neither A., nor anyone else could find fault. The use of masks must have worked against variations of character within the play." They are much more numerous than Lucas would have it; Neoptolemus undergoes no real change, but is, on the opposite, true to his fuai;, which Aristotle could not have failed to observe; the masks in the 5th c. were neutral in expression. Taran 2012, 267 comments on the meaning of ^ ksTsuouaa and Moerbecke's Lt. transl. ministrans (Minio-Paluello [1953] noted, that his ms probably read oiKsTsuouaa).

8 McDonald 1990, 69-84.

9 Stockert 1992, a study in 'change of mind' in Greek tragedy, Gibert 1995, along with a swell of articles; see McDonald 1990, 69-70, n. 1 for an overview, and also Funke 1964, Knox 1966, Sansone 1991. For more exotic interpretations, see McDonald 1990, 69, n. 1.

itself known; and the thinking of one being worthy of great things is a sign of high-minded-

ness, this is a quality of one hopeful)."

(Transl. mine)

However, these insights did not find their way into the Poetics, and it seems to be not due to any dearth of understanding on part of Aristotle of the behaviour he so keenly observed elsewhere.

A number of arguments for Iphigenia's integrity were offered by scholars of the last decades out of the dramatic situation itself: B. Knox holds that "the change of mind has been well prepared for in Euripides' play — it comes as the climax of a series of swift and sudden changes of decision which is unparalleled in ancient drama",10 (which is, however, no definite proof), with J. Gibert even establishing a pattern of mind-change, into which Iphigenia's decision will fit;11 D. Sansone is likewise kind to Iphigenia and her poet, suggesting that "witnessing the willingness of Achilles (who is in a situation similar to her own) to die for her sake, she is emotionally transformed"12 (it pays to remember that Achilles promises are verbal gymnastics), while W. Stockert holds that the simplicity of a girl whose hopes of marriage were frustrated gave way to a more mature decision due to the changed circumstances.13

Aristotle however, is not alone in his censure: H. Funke in a sound piece of criticism held that Iphigenia speaks not with her own words and not from her own mind, but was deluded by the rhetoric of her deceitful father, thus making the wrong choice for the wrong reason;14 H. Siegel observes a case of "self-delusion", making the best out of a hopeless case, while M. Lefkowitz disposes of the situation in terms of "consent turned into a free choice".15

Among the multitude of interpretations and justifications which tend to be off the point, a sound view expressed by A. Lesky and supported by J. C. Kamerbeek16 seems to be the only feasible solution: while astutely observing the qualities of young people in life (the passage in the Rhetoric 1389a-b cited above is easy proof), Aristotle could not suffer these in tragedy.

Moreover, his very terminology may not be sufficient and its application overstrict; being theoretically well-grounded it is often incapacitated when it comes to fitting in the examples, and, as a result, there is evidently little to no place for the dramatically very effective (thus TpayiKwraroc; of 1453a 29-30) lability of a Euripidean character.

References

Bywater I. (ed., transl., comment.) Aristotle on the Art of Poetry. Oxford, OUP, 1909. Diggle J. (ed.) Euripidis fabulae tomus III. Oxonii, OUP, 1994.

Else G. F. (ed., comm.) Aristotle's Poetics: The Argument. Cambridge, Mass., CUP, 1957. Funke H. Aristoteles zu Euripides' Iphigeneia in Aulis. Hermes 1964, 92, 284-299. Gibert J. Change of Mind in Greek Tragedy, Hypomnemata 108, 1995. Günther H. Ch. Euripides Iphigenia Aulidensis. Leipzig, Teubner, 1988.

10 Knox 1966, 229.

11 Gibert 1995, 240.

12 Sansone 1991, 165.

13 Stockert 1992, 26-37.

14 Funke 1964, 298-299.

15 Lefkowitz 1986, 95.

16 Lesky 1958, 146, with discussion 151-152.

Kassel R. (ed.) Aristotelis De arte poetica liber. Oxford, OUP, 1965.

Knox B. M. W. Second Thoughts in Greek Tragedy. GRBS 1966, 7, 213-232.

Kovacs D. Toward a Reconstruction of "Iphigenia Aulidensis". JHS 2003, 123, 77-103.

Kovacs D. (rev.) The OCT Euripides, CR 1998, 48, 270-272.

Lefkowitz M. Women in Greek Myth. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins UP, 1986.

Lesky A. Psychologie bei Euripides, in: Entretiens sur l'antiquité classique, Tome VI, Euripide. Vandoeuvres-Genève, Fondation Hardt, 1958, 123-168.

Lucas D. W. (comm.) Aristotle, "Poetics". Oxford, OUP, 21972.

Markland J. (ed., not.) Euripidis Supplices mulieres, Iphigenia in Aulide et in Tauris. Oxonii, OUP, 1811.

Mastronarde D. (rev.) Euripidis Fabulae, tomus III by J. Diggle: Euripides: Cyclops, Alcestis, Medea by David Kovacs. CJ 1996-1997, 92, 201-206.

Minio-Paluello L. (ed.) Aristoteles. De Arte Poetica Guillelmo de Moerbeke interprete. Bruges — Paris, Des-clée de Brouwer, 1953.

McDonald M. Iphigenia's Philia: Motivation in Euripides' Iphigenia in Aulis. Quaderni Urbinati di Cultura Classica 1990, 34, 69-84.

Ross W. D. (ed.) Aristotelis ars rhetorica. Oxonii, OUP, 1964.

Sansone D. Iphigeneia Changes Her Mind. ICS 1991, 16, 161-172.

Schmitt A. (übers., erl.) Aristoteles. Poetik. Berlin, Akademie Verlag, 2008.

Schoder R. V. Literary Sources cited by Aristotle in the Poetics. CJ 1969, 65, 75.

Stockert W. (ed., comment.) Euripides Iphigenie in Aulis, Bd. I-II. Wiener Studien, Bh. 16. Wien, Verlag der ÖAdW, 1992.

Taran L., Gutas D. (eds). Aristotle Poetics. Editio Maior of the Greek Text with Historical Introductions and Philological Commentaries. Mnemosyne Suppl. 338. Leiden — Boston, Brill, 2012.

von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff U. Einleitung in die Griechische Tragödie. Berlin, Weidmann, 1906.

Received: August 24, 2020 Accepted: November 3, 2020

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.