Научная статья на тему 'WERE HOMERIC GLOSSES PART OF SCHOOL EDUCATION IN FIFTH-CENTURY ATHENS? NEW INTERPRETATION OF ARISTOPHANES’ DAITALES FR. 233'

WERE HOMERIC GLOSSES PART OF SCHOOL EDUCATION IN FIFTH-CENTURY ATHENS? NEW INTERPRETATION OF ARISTOPHANES’ DAITALES FR. 233 Текст научной статьи по специальности «Языкознание и литературоведение»

CC BY
12
4
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
Журнал
Philologia Classica
Scopus
ВАК
Ключевые слова
ARISTOPHANES’ DAITALES / SCHOOL EDUCATION / GLOSSES / SOPHISTS / ANCIENT LINGUISTIC THEORIES

Аннотация научной статьи по языкознанию и литературоведению, автор научной работы — Chepel Elena Yu.

В статье предлагается новое прочтение фрагмента 233 (по изданию Касселя-Остина) несохранившейся комедии Аристофана «Пирующие». Этот фрагмент в научной литературе часто приводится в качестве свидетельства того, что афинская молодежь V в. до н. э. заучивала в школе глоссы из поэм Гомера. В статье подробно разбирается контекст цитирования Аристофана Галеном, степень сохранности текста фр. 233 и существующие интерпретации данного отрывка из комедии. Автор отмечает, что в самом тексте ничто прямо не указывает на принадлежность глосс к обязательной школьной программе в Афинах. Напротив, можно утверждать, что Аристофан преподносит глоссы как определенное лингвистическое новаторство, а интеллектуалов, изучающих их, как представителей нового модного движения софистов. В качестве аргументации нового прочтения фрагмента автор статьи приводит параллели между комедиями Аристофана «Пирующие» и «Облака», а также параллели с диалогом Платона «Кратил». В заключении автор предлагает переосмыслить диалог между Отцом и Сыном в фр. 233 и делает вывод о действующих лицах «Пирующих» и их роли в сюжете комедии: Старик-отец не противится софистическим учениям, а использует их в споре, чтобы показать Распутнику-сыну его невежество. В свою очередь этот сын не является последователем софистов и их нововведений, как обычно считается, и защищается от нападок отца с помощью своих знаний юридических терминов и таким образом выступает как представитель традиционной и почтенной профессии судебного оратора.The article revisits Aristophanes’ Daitales fr. 233 which is often taken as (the only) evidence of Homeric glosses being drilled by Athenian youth as part of their school education in 5th c. BC. The author discusses in detail the context of Aristophanic citation in Galen’s work, the state of the text of the fragment and its modern interpretations. In fact, nothing in the text itself directly suggests that learning glosses was part of the traditional school education in Athens. On the contrary, it can be argued that Aristophanes presented glosses as linguistic innovations and intellectuals studying them as sophists. The parallels between Daitales and Clouds, as well as Plato’s Kratylos and other fifth-century texts must be taken into account when interpretingthe dialogue between the Father and his Son in fr. 233. As a conclusion, the author suggests that the characters of Daitales should be interpreted differently: the Old Man in this episode of the play is not opposing the sophistic teachings, but rather using these in his argument as an instrument to demonstrate the Licentious Son his ignorance. The latter is apparently not a follower of the sophists and defends himself with his more practical knowledge of legal terms.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.

Текст научной работы на тему «WERE HOMERIC GLOSSES PART OF SCHOOL EDUCATION IN FIFTH-CENTURY ATHENS? NEW INTERPRETATION OF ARISTOPHANES’ DAITALES FR. 233»

UDC 82

Philologia Classica. 2022. Vol. 17. Fasc. 2

Were Homeric Glosses Part of

School Education in Fifth-century Athens?

New Interpretation of Aristophanes' Daitales fr. 233*

Elena Yu. Chepel

A. M. Gorky Institute of World Literature of the Russian Academy of Sciences, 25a, Povarskaya ul., Moscow, 121069, Russian Federation; euchepel@gmail.com

For citation: Chepel E. Yu. Were Homeric Glosses Part of School Education in Fifth-century Athens? New Interpretation of Aristophanes' Daitales fr. 233. Philologia Classica 2022, 17 (2), 244-252. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu20.2022.204

The article revisits Aristophanes' Daitales fr. 233 which is often taken as (the only) evidence of Homeric glosses being drilled by Athenian youth as part of their school education in 5th c. BC. The author discusses in detail the context of Aristophanic citation in Galen's work, the state of the text of the fragment and its modern interpretations. In fact, nothing in the text itself directly suggests that learning glosses was part of the traditional school education in Athens. On the contrary, it can be argued that Aristophanes presented glosses as linguistic innovations and intellectuals studying them as sophists. The parallels between Daitales and Clouds, as well as Plato's Kratylos and other fifth-century texts must be taken into account when interpreting the dialogue between the Father and his Son in fr. 233. As a conclusion, the author suggests that the characters of Daitales should be interpreted differently: the Old Man in this episode of the play is not opposing the sophistic teachings, but rather using these in his argument as an instrument to demonstrate the Licentious Son his ignorance. The latter is apparently not a follower of the sophists and defends himself with his more practical knowledge of legal terms.

Keywords: Aristophanes' Daitales, school education, glosses, sophists, ancient linguistic theories.

Aristophanes' Daitales fr. 2331 is often cited as evidence of Homeric glosses being part of the traditional paideia in fifth-century Athens. In this article, I would like to revisit the interpretation of this fragment and argue for an alternative understanding that sees glosses rather as part of innovative sophistic practices than of conservative education of the youth. I first present the text of the fragment with critical apparatus2 and translation, followed by the context in which it is cited; then briefly discuss the state of the text and the place of the fragment in Galen's Glossary of rare words in Hippokrates' writings (Ttov 'InnoKpatou; yXwaawv ¿^ynaic); and ultimately proceed to my main argument:

(A) npo; tauta; S'au Xs^ov 'O^pou Y^ttac;- Ti KaXoum Kopu^a; uu — uu — uu — uu — ti KaXoua' &^svr|va Kapr|va;

* The article was written in the framework of the project "Digital commentaries to ancient texts: ancient Greek comedy" financially supported by the grant of the Government of the Russian Federation No. 075-15-2021-571. I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for helpful comments.

1 Number according to Kassel-Austin edition.

2 Ap. crit. is based on K.-A. with some changes. The sigla of Galen's codd. follow Perilli 2017. © St Petersburg State University, 2022

(B) 6 [i£v ouv сто;, ¿цос; 5' оито; а5еАфо; фрастатш- Ti каАоистгу 15иои^; uu — uu — uu — uu — u onusiv;

1 таита; 5'au Poll.: таита; au Perilli: таитак; 5' au Wilamowitz, prob. Cassio: таита ctoi A: тайта сти Bas.H et Bergk Äs^ov Poll. et р: Äs^wv A. 'Оц^рои Poll.: "Оцг|ре А: (сти А.) 'Оцг|Р£юис; Seidler: (сти А.) 'Оц^рои ¿цо! Bergk. уАштта; Ti Poll.: уАйттастпка A: уАшттапка vel. уАшт-та Ti ка! N: уАйтта Tivü R: уАа>ттг| Tiv! Bas.G+H- каАойст1 codd.: каАепш Poll. корицРа Poll., Helmreich: кориРа A 2 каАоистгу codd.: каАойст' Seidler metri gratia 3 15иои; Fritzsche: l5utou;; <е!т'> Seidler: 15ои стгге А: !5ой ctoi N: !5оист1 те Ald.: е!5ойст1 те ERU 4 Ti пот^стт!у onusiv Kaibel: Ti лоте ¿ctti то еи noistv A et Cassio inter cruces: toünuav Dobree: Ti каАой-ctiv onuieiv Dindorf: Ti каАоистгу änoivav Bergk: Ti пот^сттгу änoivav Fauth

"- Now, in addition to these, tell me about Homeric glosses: what is 'aplustres'? ... What is 'strengthless heads'?

— No — let your son, this brother of mine, explain: what is 'beholders'? ... 'to espouse'"?3

öti уар ¿noiouv o[ паАаю! поААа twv övoцdтшv аитоТ;, 5е5е1.кта1 ^v kavü; ка! про; 'Eрaтoст9£vou; ¿v тоТ; Пер! арха!а; кшцф51а;, 5е!^а1Ц1 5' av ctoi кау^ vüv 5ia ßрax£шv ¿п! пaрa5еlYЦdтшv ипер той у^шсткегу ¿vaрY£CTтерov, oIov ^v ti ^ уАйтта ¿cttiv,

oIov 5s ti ка! то парапА^стю^ айт^ то YеYovö; ипо тгуо; TÖ>v лаАа10>и voцííш 5^ сто1 та ипо AрlCTTOфdvou; аркестегу та ¿к TÖ>v АаггаАеш^ 65s пш; e^vTa^ (line 1) про; — к6рuцßa; прораААе1 уар ¿v ¿кегуф тф 5рацат1 6 ¿к той 5^цou TÖ>v Аап"аА£ш^ престрит^; тф акоАасттф те! прйлш ^v та «к6рuцßa» Ti пот' ¿ctt!v ¿^г|7Пстаст9а1, цета 5е тойто (line 2) т! — карг^а- какегуо; ^vtoi ävтlпрoßdААеl twv ¿v тоТ; а^ост1 уАштто^ е!;

5!ка; 51афероиста; w5i пш; (line 3) 6 — ¡^utau;. е1т' ¿фе^; прораААе1 (line 4) Ti — опиегу. ¿^ 6v 5^Аov ш; ^ уАйтта паАаО ¿cttiv övoцa т^; CTuvr^ia; ¿кпептшко; (Gal. gloss. Hipocr., Vol. XIX, 65-66 Kühn [Perilli 2017, 145-147]).

"It was sufficiently shown by Eratosthenes in his books On Old Comedy that ancient authors indeed coined many words for the purposes of their writings, and I shall be also able to show you now briefly with the help of few examples, in order to achieve a clearer distinction, what is a gloss, and what is — something similar to it — a coinage by one of the ancient authors. I believe, some examples from Aristophanes will be enough for you, namely, from the Daitales, that read somehow as follows: (line 1). You see, in this play, an old man from the deme of Daitales challenges his licentious son to explain first of all what 'aplustres' are, and then: (line 2). The son, in his turn, suggests as counter argument some of the important legal glosses in the wooden tablets of Solon, as follows: (line 3). And after that he suggests: (line 4). From these examples, it is clear that a gloss is an old word that has fallen out of usage".

аААа ка! та; поиска; фш^а; уАштта; ¿кdÄouv ш; Aрl.сттoфdvr|с;■ про; — к6рuцßа. "But they [comic authors] also used the word glosses for poetic phrases, as in Aristophanes: (line 1)" (Poll. 2. 109).

The fragment is cited in the preface to the Glossary. In this проо^цю^ addressing his fellow citizen and classmate Teuthras,4 Galen sets forth that the main subject of his work is уАшттац obsolete words. He adds that he intends to include not only glosses in this sense, but also neologisms, öv6цата rnivd. These are words, he explains, that did not circulate in the customary usage of language but were introduced by Hippokrates either by

3 Translation is mine.

4 Cf. Gal. Ind. 34-35, Ven. Sect. Er. Rom. 11. 193. 7. He is also the addressee of Puis. 8. 452. Philologia Classica. 2022. Vol. 17. Fasc. 2 245

using common words metaphorically (^eteveyKwv &no toti auv^Gouc) or by altering the grammatical form of the word (ax^a nepiGel; etepov)5 or by changing the meaning (to a^^atvov unaXXa^ac). These neologisms are similar to glosses (to napanX^aiov autfl (sc. tfl yXwrtfl), to yeyovo; uno tivo; twv naXaiwv) because of their rare usage and, hence, obscurity.6 Having said that Aristophanes' Daitales would have enough examples for the matters being discussed, Galen cites fr. 233 where four glosses from Homer and Solon/archaic legal texts occur. The citation is complemented with a brief account about the play's plot and characters. Galen then defines a gloss as "an old word that has fallen out of usage" and proceeds to illustrate the second type of words under consideration, neologisms, choosing for this purpose fr. 205, another dialogue between the Old Man and his Son.

We do not know whether Galen used the full text of the play or picked passages from an existing compendium of excerpts or a treatise on glosses, although the latter is more plausible. On one hand, Galen's interest in and knowledge of Old Comedy must have been exceptional, which partly can be explained by his own taste and partly by professional reasons.7 We know from Ind. 23-28 that he compiled a vocabulary of nouns from "the entire of Old Comedy", being an epitome of Didymos' (presumably, Chalkenteros) fifty books on expressions in Old Comedy. This work covered both common and rare terms.8 Galen also supposes that the loss of this work in the great fire of Rome would be particularly distressing for the addressee of the treatise, assumingly, because the excerpts from comedy would facilitate reading and understanding of Hippokrates' writings. Furthermore, to illustrate the benefit of comedy for medics, Galen gives an example how he once used a comic word to resolve a medical problem.9 In another work, Galen explains that Hippokrates' obscure words can be best elucidated through studying the examples of comic language because Attic comedy based its language on the customary usage of language, auv^Geia, the linguistic term which he also uses to define glosses in the preface to the Glossary.10 On the other hand, if even for his fundamental work on comedy Galen relied on compilatory texts, he could have used one of those also for the preface to his Glossary. The reference to Eratosthenes' work On Old Comedy before the two examples from Daitales might be an indication of his source in this particular case.

The attractiveness of frr. 205 and 233 for Galen should be sought, above all, in their accessibility for readers who are unexperienced in linguistic matters. The addressee of the preface, Teuthras, was a professional physician, and hardly could engage with the language on the abstract level to the same extent as Galen did. Thus, comedy was definitely of help. While Galen was acquainted with linguistic studies of his time — besides glossaries, he

5 The ancient term for grammatical form is axrj|ia Ai^swt;. Change of the grammatical form was recognised to be a device for evoking laughter, Kaibel p. 51 n. 16.

6 Gal. gloss. Hipocr., Vol. XIX, p. 66 Kühn = Perilli p. 144.

7 See Coker 2019, esp. The list of quotations from comedy in Galen's works, 68-70.

8 In the two catalogues of his own writings, Ord. lib. and Lib. prop., however, his works on comedy are presented differently: there are three books of comic expressions, one for each of major playwrights: Eupo-lis, Aristophanes, Kratinos, and two general books, one with examples of words found only in comedy, and another titled 'If Old comedy is useful reading for students'. The explanation might be that after the loss of the compendium in the fire, Galen managed to restore it only partly and the structure had to be altered. See Coker 2019 and Boudon-Millet et al. 2010, xxxvii and 76; Olson 2017, 88-89.

9 Ind. 20-29, Daitales fr. 208.

10 Med. Nom., 31-31 MS. See on Galen's use of this term Manetti 2009.

wrote also theoretical philological treatises11 — his audience was far less competent and needed an introduction that would be easy to understand and to remember: || aot |ovov, äXAä Kai rot; aXAoi; rot; xä npwxa ypamaxa |£|a0nKoai xp|tfi|6v eivat to ßtßXiov (68 Kühn = 148 Perilli).

The lines from Aristophanes are cited by Galen to illustrate what a gloss is. Since Pollux also cites the first line of fr. 233 as an example of a poetic gloss, it is probable that both authors used a common source, perhaps, even Eratosthenes, to whom Galen refers. Remarkably, the dramatic lines chosen do not simply contain obsolete words, but also identify them as glosses and further thematise them in a way that demonstrates, underlines and, in the end, mocks their uncommonness in the language, which makes this excerpt from Daitales particularly suitable to serve as a textbook example for a philological clarification of different types of poetic words.12 It is also important for Galen's explanation that the quoted text refers to the ancient authors who had used words that later became glosses: Homer and Solon. Aristophanes' text thus functions here, on one hand, as an ancient and, therefore, authoritative, source of glosses itself, and, on the other hand, as a linguistic discussion of the glosses in works of ancient authors, at which Galen himself aims in his Glossary.

Galen's comments on the dialogue shape our understanding of the fragment. He names the characters speaking, the Old Man and the Licentious Son, interprets their conversation as an argument, and provides additional information which the text of the fragment itself does not contain, such as the attribution of the glosses to Solon. The context, thus, on one hand gives additional details and clues on reading and understanding the fragment. On the other hand, Galen's comments require a critical approach, as they are his own reader's view of the fragment and of the play.13 The question to which extent Galen's account of the fragment and the play in general is accurate remains open. For instance, we trust Galen's distribution of speech between characters, although, if he did not possess his own copy of the play and took the citation from a compendium, a confusion of which line belongs to which character would be possible. After all, Galen was most likely wrong about the deme of Daitales from which, he reports, the Old Man came, and which is not attested as an Athenian deme elsewhere.

The text of the citations in the mss is significantly damaged. The first line is attested also in Pollux, who gives better readings. Perilli argues that only the last word in line 4 should be attributed to Aristophanes, while the rest is paraphrase by Galen since it repeats his earlier phrasing about Kopu|ßa. This also means that the place of onuetv in the line is not certain. The first half of the second line probably contained one more gloss.

The metre suggests that these verses may have been part of the agon. The standard interpretation can be traced back to Fritzsche's commentary or earlier and is as follows: the Old Man is attacking his Licentious Son, challenging him to explain some obscure Homeric glosses, since learning these was part of traditional Athenian education. He speaks in a condescending manner, as a teacher or adult would talk to a child. The son, in an attempt to defend himself, suggests that his brother, the Virtuous Son, explains instead some

11 Soph., Capt., nspi aacpr|v£Îaç Kal àaaçeiaç, El Ôûvarai tic; dvai KprnKoç Kai ypa^ariKÔç, npoç toùç ÊniTi^wvraç toïç aoXoïKÎÇoum Tfj cpwvfj. On Galen's philological expertise, see Hanson 1998.

12 Cf. Strato Phoenicides fr. 1 thematising Homeric style and glosses used in a papyrus textbook in Ptolemaic Egypt, P. Cair. inv. 65445, Guéraud-Jouguet 1938.

13 See also on this problem Novokhatko 2017, 237-238.

legal expressions. The Licentious Son redirects the question since he himself is ignorant about the answer, that is, lacks elementary school knowledge, although he spends all his time studying new fashionable sophistic teachings. The Old Man and the Virtuous Son, on the contrary, being exponents of the old education, are familiar with Homeric diction but are ignorant of legal vocabulary that is used in speeches of the time. This interpretation, in our opinion, needs to be revisited.

The fragment has been frequently quoted in scholarship as a source on fifth-century Athenian education. In particular, it has been suggested that fr. 233 attests the drill of Homeric glosses as part of school curriculum.14 It is true that memorizing and reciting poems was an element of traditional education, and young people had to learn Homeric poems by heart (npo^aGeiv).15 In Clouds, the old-style education is illustrated through monotonous repetition of poems after the teacher, in order to memorize them (npo^aGeiv, Nu. 966-967). This image is different from discerning and understanding rare Homeric words which requires certain critical thinking and abstract notion of language. There is no direct evidence neither that glosses received special attention as standard exercise at that time, nor that they circulated in lists or textbooks.16 Therefore, the possibility should be considered that in fr. 233 Homeric glosses are the opposite of the old paideia: a sophistic innovation.

In fact, Homeric texts were of great interest for fifth-century sophists. The juxtaposition between traditional and sophistic ways of reading Homer is shown in Xen. Symp. 3. 5-6: sophists sought to understand the true meanings of Homeric poems, not to learn them by heart as stupid rhapsodes, £0voq ^AiGiwtepov pa^wSwv, a disdainful expression of Sokrates' disciple Antisthenes. According to Protagoras in Pl. Prot., the early poets, such as Homer, Hesiod and Simonides, were first sophists who used their poetry as a cover-up for their real purpose (Prot. 316D).17 In this dialogue, sophists compete with Sokrates about moral meanings of poetic texts. This adaptation of archaic poets for sophistic argument is reflected in Nu. 1057, where the Unjust Speech cites Homer, arguing that the great poet approved of the art of public speeches at the agora by portraying Nestor an orator (Il. 1. 248; 4. 293). The word he uses, ayoprfT^c;, is a Homeric gloss and does not occur in fifth-century texts besides Clouds.

It is not accidental that Aristophanes chose the figure of Nestor for illustrating the sophistic argument. Nestor seems to have been popular in intellectual discussions of the time. In the passage from Xen. Symp. mentioned above, Nikeratos, who was extensively educated on Homer by the sophists, enthusiastically quotes Nestor's speech from the Iliad (23. 335-337). The Homeric verse on Nestor lifting his cup (Il. 11. 636-637) was especially attractive for sophistic debates on interpretation: Porphyry in his scholia to the Iliad reports how Antisthenes and Stesimbrotos understood it (schol. in Il A 636, Antisthenes fr. 191 Gianantonni). Hippias of Elis wrote Trojan Dialogue in which Nestor instructs Ne-optolemos about how to gain a good reputation.

14 Cassio 1977, 29 and 75: "questi versi, che appratengono certamente a un agone, ci confermano che l'apprendimento delle glosse omeriche e della corrispondente spiegazione era parte integrante del curriculum di studi nell' insegnamento elementare". Cf. Dunbar 1998, 293; Revermann 2013, 111.

15 Pl. Prot. 325e, Leg. 810e-11a, Xen. Symp. 3. 5; Isoc.11. 159; Aeschin. 3. 135; Ar. Ran. 1038-1039, cf. Pritchard 2015, 113-114.

16 Pfeiffer (1968, 79-80) concludes that glossographoi started their work not earlier than 3rd c. BC.

17 See discussion in Richardson 1975.

Particularly, sophists relied on literary works of Homer and other poets in their linguistic studies.18 One of the key topics of sophistic language theory was 'correctness of names', opGoeneia/ opGoxnc ovo^axwv, and by names they meant words in general and even sentences. Antisthenes who claimed that apx^ naiSeuaew; ^ xwv ovo^axwv ¿maKe^i; (Epict. Dissert. 1. 17.10-12 = fr.160 Gianantonni), wrote treatises on Homeric criticism and exegesis such as nepl OSuaaewc, nepl O^pou, nepl OSuaaea; etc (Diog. Laert. 6. 15-18 = fr.41 Gianantonni). He also interpreted in detail the Homeric epithet noXuxpono; (fr. 187 Gianantonni, Porph. schol. in Od. a 1). Demokritos, the teacher of Protagoras, wrote a treatise on opGoeneia with the title nepl O^pou ^ 'OpGoeneqc Kal yXwaaewv, implying a distinction between the correct usage of words and Homeric obsolete vocabulary. The term yXWxxa itself was probably freshly coined around the time of the performance of Daitales.19

Protagoras, who is according to the opinio communis mocked in Clouds, developed the theory of opGoeneia as usage of words in their direct meaning, the opposition of glosses and poetic diction.20 He also applied grammatical categories, such as gender and types of discourse (wish, question, answer, command etc.) to Homeric text as an instrument of criticism (Diogenes Laertios 9.54; Arist. Poet. 1456b15-17). Another sophist, Prodikos, known for his interest in opGoxnc ovo^axwv (Pl. Prot. 341c9, Crat. 384b, 277e3-4) and subtle distinction (Siaipeaic) of synonyms, was probably inspired by Homer for his etymological hypotheses.21

It is plausible that these and other debates on the 'correct' use of words, that were in vogue in the intellectual circles in fifth-century Athens, were reflected also in Aristophanes' Daitales, as they certainly were in Clouds.22 If so, fr. 233 could have been part of a debate about the meaning and correct usage of words and/or correct interpretation of Homer which was a feature of new sophistic education. The interest in law courts, on the other hand, is more characteristic in Aristophanic comedy of the old generation, cf. Philokleon and the chorus of juries-old men in Wasps and Strepsiades in Clouds whose practical interest in winning a court case is contrasted with the abstract teaching of Sokrates and his school.

Furthermore, the verb KaXew, that is repeated three times in the fragment, has a special meaning in the light of sophistic theories of language. In Clouds, when Sokrates introduces Strepsiades to the wisdom of his school, he uses it almost as a terminus technicus of saying the correct form of the word according to its gender: Zw. opa; a naaxeic; x^v xe G^Xeiav KaXei; | aXeKxpuova Kara xauxo Kal xov appeva (662-663); Zx v^ xov noaeiSw. vtiv Se nw; ^e xp^ KaXeiv; (665); Zw. iSou ^aX' auGic, xouG' exepov^ x^v KapSonov | appeva KaXet; G^Xeiav ouaav (670-671). Olson, 2021, 196, in his translation implies the scholarly technicality of this verb: "you're referring to the male by a term also used for the female"; and for v.1258, Olson 2021, 299: (¿)KaXeaa; ... x^v KapSonov "you used the word kardo-pos". This translation is supported by the scholia: 'oxi ^v eSei ae KapSonr|v eineiv', cf. also Dover 1968, 242.

18 On sophists' linguistic activities, see Kerferd 1981, 68-77, Wolfsdorf 2015, 69; Grintser 2017, esp. 372-374 on using poetry.

19 Pfeiffer 1968, 78-79; Novokhatko 2020, 57-58; Novokhatko 2020a, 95-96.

20 Pl. Phdr.267c. See Grintser 2017, 369.

21 Grintser 2017, 372-374.

22 Willi 2003, 97-105, 118-120; Kerferd 1981, 69.

The word KápSono; was later included in lexica as an Aristophanic gloss and was perhaps a rare word already in the fifth century. It could hint at some cosmological teaching of sophists (cf. Pl. Phaed. 99b 10). Sokrates' preoccupation with the gender of the word in this scene — the feminine form of KápSono;, KapSónn, was probably coined by Aristophanes — alludes to Protagoras who was concerned with the grammatical category of gender and with the correct use of gender. This parody of sophistic teachings is significant in the play, as it re-appears again at the end of the play when Strepsiades applies the fruits of his sophistic education to a real-life task (1248-1258). The scene in Clouds is, therefore, a close parallel to fr. 233, featuring linguistic theories of sophists and discussing separate words in a qua-si-school context that is essential for the plot and thematical structure of the play. It is possible that the use of KaAiw in fr. 233 is not accidental and hints at sophistic theories of ovo^ata.

Moreover, it seems that the verb KaAiw might have been a marker of sophistic language debates.23 Plato's Kratylos, which is dedicated to sophistic language theory and has the subtitle 'about the correctness of names' (nepl óvo^áxwv ópOóT^roc;), opens with Kratylos' proposition on the 'correctness of names' which uses emphatically the verb KaAiw with ovo^a as its object: EPM. KpaTÚXo; 9^alv oSe, w ZwKpaTe;, óvó^aTo; ópOÓT^ta eívai ÉKáaTW T«v ovTwv ^úaet ne^uKutav, Kal oü toüto eívai ovo^a o av Tive; auvGé^evot KaXetv KaXwat, t^; aÚTwv ^óptov ém^GeyYó^evoi, aAAa ópGóT^Tá Tiva twv

óvo^áTwv ne^uKévat Kal"EWnai Kal ^ap^ápot; T^v aÚT^v anaaiv. After that, throughout the dialogue, this verb is used passim to argue about the meanings and etymologies of separate words.24 Similarly, it is used in the scene in Xen. Mem. 3,14, 2-5 where the meaning and etymology of words are discussed.

In the light of these parallels, it seems plausible that both the Old Man and his Virtuous Son were followers of the new sophistic movement, whereas the Licentious Son was adherent to traditional and more practical legal education. The Old Man is proud of his knowledge of obscure words in Homer and exposes his Son's ignorance, while the latter finds this kind of expertise ridiculous and redirects the question to some legal terms, which, in his opinion, are much more relevant in real life.

Bibliography

Barney R. Names and nature in Plato's Cratylus. Studies in philosophy. New York — London, Routledge, 2001. Bergk T. Aristophanisfragmenta. Berlin, Reimer, 1840.

Boudon-Millot V., Jouanna J., Pietrobelli A. (eds) Galien. Nepas se chagriner. Paris, Les Belles Lettres, 2010. Cassio A. C. (ed., comm.) Aristofane, Banchettanti (Daitales): i frammenti. Pisa, Giardini, 1977. Coker A. Galen and the Language of Old Comedy: Glimpses of a Lost Treatise at Ind. 23b-28, in: C. Petit (ed.) Galen's Treatise nepl 'AXvnlac, (De indolentia) in Context: A Tale of Resilience. Leiden, Brill, 2019, 63-90.

Dindorf G. Aristophanis fragmenta. Leipzig, Libraria Weidmannia, 1829.

Dindorf G. Poetarum scenicorum graecorum... fabulae superstites etperditarum fragmenta. Leipzig, Teubner, 1869.

Dobree, see Scholefield Dover 1968: K. J. Dover, Aristophanes' Clouds (Oxford). Dunbar N. Aristophanes' Birds. Oxford, OUP, 1998.

Fritzsche F. De Daetalensibus Aristophanis commentatio. Leipzig, Lehnhold, 1831.

Grintser N. The Birth of European Linguistic Theory: The Idea of Language in the Sophists, in: T. Li, K. Dyer (eds) From Ancient Manuscripts to Modern Dictionaries: Select Studies in Aramaic, Hebrew, and Greek. Piscataway, NJ, 2017, 365-378.

23 See also Willi 2003, 64, 84 n. 85, on this verb indicating the technical status of a word in comedy.

24 See Sedley 2003, 51-54 and Barney 2001, 26-29, on the implications of 'calling' in Kratylos.

Guéraud O., Jouguet P. Un livre d'écolier du Ille siècle avant J.-C. Cairo, Société Royale Égyptienne de Papyrologie, 1938.

Hanson A. E. Galen: author and critic, in: G. Most (ed.) Editing texts — Texte edieren. Gottingen, Vanden-

hoeck & Ruprecht, 1998, 22-53. Kaibel G. Comicorum Graecorum Fragmenta. Berlin, Weidmann, 1899. Kerferd G. B. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge, CUP, 1981. Kuhn K. G. (ed.) Claudii Galeni Opera omnia. Lipsiae, Car. Cnoblochii, 1821-1833.

Manetti D. Galen and Hippocratic medicine: language and practice, in: C. Gill, T. Whitmarsh, J. Wilkins

(eds) Galen and the world of knowledge. Cambridge, CUP, 2009, 157-174. Novokhatko A. Discourse markers in a comic fragmentary dialogue, in: F. Logozzo, P. Poccetti (eds) Ancient Greek Linguistics: New Approaches, Insights, Perspectives. Berlin — Boston, De Gruyter, 2017, 227-242. Novokhatko A. The Origins and Growth of Scholarship in Pre-Hellenistic Greece, in: F. Montanari (ed.) History of Ancient Greek Scholarship. From the Beginnings to the End of the Byzantine Age. Leiden — Boston, Brill, 2020, 9-131.

Novokhatko A. Homeric Hermeneutics on the way from Athens to Alexandria, in: A. Rengakos, P. Finglass, B. Zimmermann (eds) More than Homer Knew — Studies on Homer and His Ancient Commentators. Berlin — Boston, De Gruyter, 2020, 87-171. Olson S. D. (comm.) Eupolis. Testimonia and Aiges — Dêmoi (frr. 1-146). Translation and Commentary. Heidelberg, Verlag Antike, 2017. Olson S. D. (comm.) Aristophanes' Clouds: A Commentary. Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 2021. Perilli L. Galeni vocum Hippocratis Glossarium / Galeno, Interpretazione delle parole difficili di Ippocrate.

Testo, Traduzione e Note di Commento. Berlin — Boston, De Gruyter, 2017. Pfeiffer R. History of classical scholarship: from the beginnings to the end of the Hellenistic age. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1968.

Pritchard D. M. Athens, in: W. M. Bloomer (ed.) A Companion to Ancient Education. Chichester, Wiley-Black-well, 2015, 112-122.

Revermann 2013: M. Revermann M. Paraepic comedy: point(s) and practices, in: E. L. Prauscello, M. Telo (eds) Comic Interactions: Comedy and Other Genres. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013, 101-128.

Richardson N. J. Homeric professors in the age of the Sophists. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological

Society 1975, 21, 65-81. Scholefield J. (ed.) Dobree Petri Pauli Advresaria ll. Cambridge, 1843. Sedley D. Plato's Cratylus. New York, Cambridge University Press, 2003. Seidler A. Brevis disputatio de Aristophanis fragmentis. Halle, Paxonum, 1818.

Willi A. The languages of Aristophanes. Aspects of Linguistic variation in classical Attic Greek. Oxford, OUP, 2003.

Wolfsdorf D. Sophistic Method and Practice, in: W. M. Bloomer (ed.) A Companion to Ancient Education. Chichester, Wiley-Blackwell, 2015, 63-76.

Были ли гомеровские глоссы частью школьного образования в Афинах V в.? Новое прочтение фр. 233 «Пирующих» Аристофана*

Елена Юрьевна Чепель

Институт мировой литературы им. А. М. Горького РАН,

Российская Федерация, 121069, Москва, ул. Поварская, 25а; euchepel@gmail.com

Для цитирования: Chepel E. Yu. Were Homeric Glosses Part of School Education in Fifth-century Athens? New Interpretation of Aristophanes' Daitales fr. 233. Philologia Classica 2022, 17 (2), 244-252. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu20.2022.204

В статье предлагается новое прочтение фрагмента 233 (по изданию Касселя-Остина) несохранившейся комедии Аристофана «Пирующие». Этот фрагмент в научной лите-

* Работа подготовлена при поддержке Правительства РФ (проект № 075-15-2021-571 «Цифровые комментарии к античным текстам: древнегреческая комедия»).

ратуре часто приводится в качестве свидетельства того, что афинская молодежь V в. до н. э. заучивала в школе глоссы из поэм Гомера. В статье подробно разбирается контекст цитирования Аристофана Галеном, степень сохранности текста фр. 233 и существующие интерпретации данного отрывка из комедии. Автор отмечает, что в самом тексте ничто прямо не указывает на принадлежность глосс к обязательной школьной программе в Афинах. Напротив, можно утверждать, что Аристофан преподносит глоссы как определенное лингвистическое новаторство, а интеллектуалов, изучающих их, как представителей нового модного движения софистов. В качестве аргументации нового прочтения фрагмента автор статьи приводит параллели между комедиями Аристофана «Пирующие» и «Облака», а также параллели с диалогом Платона «Кратил». В заключении автор предлагает переосмыслить диалог между Отцом и Сыном в фр. 233 и делает вывод о действующих лицах «Пирующих» и их роли в сюжете комедии: Старик-отец не противится софистическим учениям, а использует их в споре, чтобы показать Распутнику-сыну его невежество. В свою очередь этот сын не является последователем софистов и их нововведений, как обычно считается, и защищается от нападок отца с помощью своих знаний юридических терминов и таким образом выступает как представитель традиционной и почтенной профессии судебного оратора. Ключевые слова: Пирующие, Аристофан, школьное образование, глоссы, софисты, античные теории языка.

Received: 15.05.2022

Accepted: 23.09.2022

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.