Научная статья на тему 'The alternative analysis: its basis, theory and some applications'

The alternative analysis: its basis, theory and some applications Текст научной статьи по специальности «Математика»

CC BY
74
27
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
Ключевые слова
EUCLIDEAN AXIOM 8 / NATURAL NUMBERS SET / CONTINUUM-HYPOTHESIS / AN INJECTION / A SEQUENCE OF NATURAL NUMBERS / A COUNTABLE SET / EXACT-PERMUTATION

Аннотация научной статьи по математике, автор научной работы — Sukhotin Alexander Mihaylovich

Let N be the positive integers set. In this paper we prove that any mapping f: N®A, with AÌN, cannot be an injective one, i. е. (AÌN)Þ(Ø(A~N)). We use the theorem about of linear n-space basis, that is there das not exists any injective mapping of basis B n+1 into a basis B n. In other words, we proved Euclidean Axiom 8: “The Whole is more than its own Part”; there are some proofs this theorem in our article

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.

Текст научной работы на тему «The alternative analysis: its basis, theory and some applications»

УДК 510, 517, 511

THE ALTERNATIVE ANALYSIS: ITS BASIS, THEORY AND SOME APPLICATIONS

Alexander Mihaylovich Sukhotin,docent, prof. RAE Тел.: 8 913 808 8066, e-mail: asukhotin@yandex.ru National Research Tomsk polytechnic university http://tpu.ru

Let N be the positive integers set. In this paper we prove that any mapping f: N^A, with AcN, cannot be an injective one, i. е. (AcN)^(-(A~N)). We use the theorem about of linear n-space basis, that is there das not exists any injective mapping of basis Bn+1into a basis Bn. In other words, we proved Euclidean Axiom 8: "The Whole is more than its own Part"; there are some proofs this theorem in our article.

Key words: Euclidean Axiom 8, natural numbers set, continuum-hypothesis, an injection, a sequence of natural numbers, a countable set, exact-permutation.

1. Introduce. We use known mathematical texts in this report and we follow the Paul Cohen's forecast about continuum-hypothesis (CH) [1, IV. 13]: «A point of view which the author feels may eventually come to be accepted is that CH is obviously false». Linear independence (dependence) is the main concept of linear space En. "If there is a finite number of vector in the basis, the space is said to be finite dimensional and its dimension is equal to the number of vectors in its basis. Otherwise, it is infinite dimensional. For an infinite dimension space a basis usually means a sequence of elements xv x2, ■■■ such that every x is uniquely expressible in the form (meaning that the limit as n becomes infinite x — ajXj is zero)". [2, p. 27] The basis Bn of En contains n linearly independent vectors and the set of any Ti -+- 1 vectors in Enare linearly dependent and there does not exist any injective mapping of basis Bn+1on En+1 into the basis Bnon En. Now we shall generalized those statements on infinite-dimensional linear spaced easily. Let F(A,B) = {f | f:A^B} be a set of all mappings [3, Sec. 8] from A in B (on B). A mapping ф:A^B is said to be injective one, or an injection, if either

a = qholds ф(а) = ф(q), or ф(1)

Instead of "the f is injective one" one speak [4, II.3.7] also, that "the f is one-to-one function" or "the f is 1-1-correcpondence". The mapping ф:A^B of this kind that ф(Л) = В is said to be "as mapping on" or "a surjective mapping", or, more shortly, "a surjection". Injective mapping ф:A^B is named as bijective mapping or bijection [4, II.7] [5, I.6] if it is surjective too, i. е., when it is true (1) and ф(Л) = В. In this case one speaks, that the sets A and B either arebijective, or they have equal power [5, I.9] and he writes A~B. The bijection ф^is named also a rearrangement, or a permutation, or a transformation of the set A. Let the symbols I(A,B), S(A,B) and B(A, B) designate the sets of injections, surjections and bijections from A in B or, accordingly, into B. So at those notations we have the following equality

B{A,B) = 1{A,B) nS(A,B). (2)

Equality (2) shows that we must confirm both two properties of a mapping ф: A^B: 1) the injectivity of ф and 2) its surjectivity ф(Л) = В, before we can say that the mapping ф:A^B is any bijection. Unfortunately, this requirement is ignored at any operating with the term (1-1)-correcpondence either implicitly, or by default. Bellow we need a criterion of a

A.M Сухвнян

bijectivity of a mapping ф: A^B being demonstrated in [6, Th.3.10], so everyone can prove that easily.

Theorem 1.Criterion of a bijectivity. The mapping ф:A^B is bijective one if and only if for every splitting of the set A = и£Л£into nonintersecting subsets Ai, i e ZcW, tree following conditions are fulfilled:

(1) Vt тарр^ф£: At ^ В is any injection, whereф£ = ф| ,

Uj

(2) V(iJ: i * j)Bi= 0, where5j = ф(Л£),

(3)U iBi=B.

However, for examples, in 1950 H. Hasse wrote [7,1.1.1], that a mapping [N U {0}} '^Шф(п) = n — 1 is a substitute". This sentence contradicts with Theorem 1 by means of uniqueness theorem for the set N existence.

2.Galileo Galilei's paradox. Now to be followed to Peano [8, 3.1] we formulate the Axioms System for the set N with the equality relation (x = x, аф b):

(P1) 0 eN.

(P2) VxeN, Bx'eN, thex' is said to be "immediately follows to x".

(Рз) VxeNxVO.

(P4) VyeN\{0}B!zeN: (z)' = y.

(P5) If any attribute Q(x) is defined VxeN, and if

(I) Q(0)=truth and

(II)VxeWQ(x)=truth holds Q(x')=truth, therefore,

(III)VyeWQ(y)=truth.

Axiom (P5) affirms the principle of mathematical induction. Below we use this mathematical induction technique every often. Galileo Galilei discovered on 1638 [9, с. 140-146; 10,IV.32] the paradox which is Va e N 3b = a2eN. G. Galilei has said about this as following: "The notions both either equality or inequality can be used only for finite qualities and not be applied for the infinite ones".

However, on the boundary of XIX and XX centuries there was appeared far-reaching with mistakes generalization of G.Galilee's opinion about his paradox. S. Kleene write down [10, IV.32] this point of view as following: " ... it is possible to establish 1-1-correcpondence between squares of the positive integers numbers and itself integers, that conflicts with Euclidian Axiom 8 [11], according to which whole more than any of its own parts. ."

Now we shall give a new interpretation of G.Galilee's paradox. To be exact yet we prove the mapping ф:М ^ N, withф(n) = n2, is not realizable on the all set N. We shall consider the square In x In, where/n = (0,1,2, ...,n). Let now S(n) be the following statement: "The ф(п) = n2is not realizable on the all In ". We prove VnGW thestatement S(n) by mathematical induction technique.

(I) Let n=2, so I2 = (0,1,2) and ф(/2) = (0,1,4)-(ф(/2) c/2 = (0,1, 2)). Then 5(2) = truth.

(11.1) Let n=k and S(k) = truth by induction.

(11.2) Let n=k+1. Then ф(/л+1) = ф(/л)иф(^ + 1). Since ф(к + 1) = (fc + 1)2 and with (II.1) ф(/л+1)-(с lk+1). Therefore,

(III) VneN,n> 1,5(n) = truth.

So we proved Euclidean Axiom 8 at the first time.

3. Stephen C. Kleene had used [12, I, 1,2] the Cantor diagonal method for the proof an uncountability of all natural sequences sets. Namely, he has chosen the countable subset of

natural sequences [f* (k) )from the set of all ones. Haskell Curry has descri-

bedthesimilar example as Rishar's paradox. Farther, S. Kleene wrote the sequences [f* (&)) in the infinite-dimensional square matrix

(3)

Further S. Kleene has defined one more sequence f*(k) under the formula

f*(k) = fk(k) + 1. Matrix H of countable subsets of the set of all se-

quences. The sequence /*(&) was not inscribed into matrix (3) because this list-matrix H was already formed as completely and so finely. And consequently Stephen C. Kleene has formulated the following statement: "The set of all number natural sequences is not countable one." Really, S. Kleene has proved much greater. He proved that there not exist any bijection between the set H of sequences /¿*(k) and set H* = H U {/*(&)} . We write below the details of some proofs of this statement.

Let Bn+1 = (b0,b1,.,bn) and Hn = (h0,h1,...,hn_1) bebases of two linear spaces Fn+1and En, accordingly. We shall use the mathematical induction techniquefor proving the following statement.

Theorem2.

VnGN3(i,j, m): i + 1,j + 1, m < n:V (9: Bn+1 ^ Hn)^>(bi) = = hm. (I) Let n=1,then Bn+1 = B2 = (b0,b1) and Hn = = (h0). Now we have following equflities: >(b0) = >>(&!) = h0, so Th. 2=truth.

(11.1) Let n=k and Th. 2 = truth, by a condition of induction.

(11.2) Let n=k+1.

Then Bn+1 = Bk+2 = (b0,blt---,bk+1),Hn = Hk+1 = (h0,b1,-,bk).Nowwe have >(Bk+2) = >(Bk+1 U {bk+1}) = >(flfc+1)u>(X&fc+1})cHfc+1. Thus 3m, m < k + 1: >(bk+1) = hmE Hk+1. At the second hand, by virtue >(Bk+1)<^Hk+1,3l,l <k + 1:>(bi) = hm. Then we have

= hm = >(&fc+1).That isTh. 2 = truth in this case too. Therefore, (III) VnsN,n> 1, Th. 2 = truth. So we proved Euclidean Axiom 8 at the second time.

4. Cantor diagonal method and Euclidean Axiom 8. Now we return to matrix (3). Let in (3)

matrix H be identity matrix HE

The lines of matrix HE are canonic natural sequences ft = (5f: k = 0,00), i = 0, oo,here 5f -is L. Kronecker symbol. Those sequences make up a basis 5(F) of infinite-dimensional space Fthat is the set of all natural sequences (/¿(fc)^= 0)^o ,i,k E N[2, p. 349]. For example, if /* = (0 1 1 0 ... ),then /* = /1 + /2. Now we identifier every element fk of basis 5(F) with the corresponding natural number kby means following bijection>: N ^ 5(F),

Let F* = 5(F) U {/*}. Now we shall prove the following main statement.

Теорема 3. There is not mapping y: F*^5(F) that is an injective one.

(1) 3m: ф(/*) = bm. (2) Yet the mapping y: 5(F) ^ B(F)\{bm} is not injective by virtue of both Theorem 1 and Theorem 2.

/ 1 0 0 0 0 ... \ 0 1 0 0 0 ...

ф(Ю =fk.

(4)

Theorem 3 is equivalent by virtue of the bijection (4) with Euclidian Axiom 8 in connection with the set N of all natural numbers in following form:

NcN U {a, U {a}~N).

The second example is more instructive: The bijective mapping exists by virtue of the bijection (4) between the set of all even natural numbers and the set, for example, those and only those vectors of the basis 5(F), which have even indexes. The legend about an existence of any bijective correspondence between of natural numbers set and the set of even numbers was constructed on any historical misunderstanding. Thus we proved Euclidean Axiom 8 once again.

1. The anti-cyclic permutation. In this item we use essentially the Axiom of Choice [1, IV.9], [13,0.23-0.26] and a notion of exact-permutation in our proofs. If / £ F(i4,i4)and H c A, then not always f(H) ^ H. A set Bex(A,A)of all exact rearrangements of a set A (exact-permutation or anti-cyclic permutation, a rearrangements without cycles [6, Chap. 3]) we define by the following equality

Bex(A,A) ±{f:fE B(A,A)}&f(H) = H * H = A. (5)

For example, the bijection f £ Bex(I,I), I=[0,1], can be defined with following formula:

A f x + h,if 0<x<1-h, /w -\i-x, if1-h<x<1,

whereh<0,5 and h is a transcendental number.

The graph of this function in the obvious image testifies, that the given function f satisfies to a condition (5). It is easy to write down exact rearrangements on set of natural numbers but what would not be the first element in image at a mapping f £ Bex(N, N),the last element there cannot be, that is obvious, by virtue of the potential nature of set N.

Now we shall choose a pair {a, y}, a £ A and y £ Bex(A, A)by means of the Axiom of a choice [13, 0.23-0.24] from sets A and Bex(N,N) . Further we define with the help of the pair {a, y} following sequence of investments of subsets of set A, named ([3, Sec. 14], [13,

0.9; 0.23]) as a chain (a chain on an investment):

{a} c (a, b} c (a, b, c}} c: (a, b, c,..., p) cc (a, b, c,..., p, q} c: ••• c A, (6)

where b = ^(a), c = d = ^(c), ..., q = ^(p), ... .

We shall name a chain (6) by a-chain on its first element [6, En. 3]. Let's emphasize, that in (6)V7cAy_1(a)£ Y, in general case. If Q and P, PcQcA, are the neighboring elements of a-chain (6), then Q=P U {q} = P+, where y(p) = q and q is, accordingly, the greatest element in Q in the sense that,Q\P = {q}. The last property defines discrete character of a chain (6). Therefore, it is obvious, that the set of elements of a-chain (6) is quite ordered set,

1. e., its each non trivial subset has the least element. We shall name a-chain (6) a full one, meaning two its properties noted above. If i,^Bex(A,A), then, at the first, ^(a)=g^a, and, secondly, the mapping £ will transform the initial full a-chain (6) into some full g-chain which we shall designate as symbolP(g, A). Thus, equality^ = P+is equivalent to equality^ = tyQ = P\J{q}, hence, we have following equalities:

£(P+K( PU{q)K(P)U £({?})=£(Q).

_^

Order v on set A is defined by pair {a,y} as follows. If h = y (a), then Vq £ A\h we accept q -P h and qP^(p). Besides if for elements Q and R of a-chain (6)3H such, that QcHcR, i. e. R^Q +, thenfor VqsQ and Vse R \ Q +we assume q - s. So that a -- b, b -- c,

c -P d , ..., where, as in (6), b=^(a), , с = -ф(Ь), d = -ф(с), ..., q = ^(p), ... . By virtue of (6) order v is both full and discrete. Set A with the order v we shall designate as (A, v).

Remark 1. If the element exists, then we can define a decreasing chain on an

investment

А з Л\{а) з Л\{а, b} з{а, b , с} з — з Л\{а, b, с, р) з Л\{а, Ь, с, ■ ■■, р, q} з - з (7)

by means of a full chain (6) by obvious image. We name a chain (7) as dual-chain for a-chain (6).

Theorem 4.V(y, Y): ysY^Athere exists ф,феВ(А,А), such thaty-chain P(y, ф, A)3Y.

Proof Let Z = A\Y,aeBex(Y,Y)andTeBex(Z,Z). Thus we have y-chain P(y, a F).LetFU{r) = F+,re5ex(Z,Z).Now we construct the феА(ДЛ) as following: 1)ф|у =

oand 2)ф|2 = т.

Using both Theorem 1 and Theorem 4 we can construct new proof of Euclid Axiom 8. Let (A, v) be a set А with order v from it.4. Further let P(A)be a set of all subsets of set A. Now we consider the class P(A))containing all elements of the set P(A), the set of all a-chains and the set of all dual-chains. Now everyone can easily prove the following statement.

Theorem 5. Any chain V, being either an own part of either some full q-chain or of the dual-chain is a well ordered one, i.e. this chainV has the least element.

6. The quite ordered sets and injective mappings. Now we prove Euclid Axiom 8 in the form of the following theorem. Теорема 6. Let BcAand феР(Д В), then such pair (a, q) of elements a and q exists into the set A, that

ф(а) = а Ф q. (8)

ProofLet фСА) = S.It will not break a generality of our reasoning. Now we shall assume opposite (8), i. е.,фе/(Д 5)^0 at BcA and let further H A A\B, then НпВ = 0. Now we have a circuit of equalitiesin those designations:

В = ф(Л) = ф(В иЯ) = ф(5) U ф(Я).

Therefore, ф(5) Q В andф(Я) Q B.An шйшюпфСЯ) Q В means, that Vft. G H and b e В exists such thatф(Л) = b.On the other hand, if ф(5) = В, then an element geSexists for every beBby virtue of фе/(Д5) such, that ф^) = b = ф(Л) at g£h, since ВпЯ = 0. This proves the condition (8). In case ф(5) = ВгcB andЯ1 = B\Blt then ф(5) = ф(В1 U Ях) = ф(В1) U ф(Я1).Therefore,ф(51) Q Вг and ф(Ях) Q B1.As well as above we prove, that eithe^^) = Вг and the condition (8) is proved, o^^) = B2cB1,H2 = 51\52and so on. Thus, we shall receive following a decreasing sequence Z of investments: АзВзВ1зВ2з.зВ1з.... Here ieJ and J is some set of indexes corresponding constructed chain Z. This chain Z contains by virtue either of Theorems 4 and 5 or Kuratowski's lemma [13, 0.25.(d)] in some maximal chain. Therefore, the chain Z has any least element in this case. It means that there 3 к eJ^(Bk_1) = Bk and ф(Вк) =BkcBk_1. If as above, Hk A Bk_1\Bk * 0, then ф{Вк_1) = ф(BkиНк) = ф(Вк)^ф(Нк) = Вк. Therefore, ф(Вк) = Вк and ф(Ял) £ Вк at ВкпНк = 0by virtue of the subsetЯfcchoice.It means that the conclusion (8) of Theorem 6 is proved. Consequently, we prove Euclidean Axiom 8 at the fourth time in this paper.

Theorem 6 has following the canonical brief form: BcA^-A~B.

In particular, (A~ (A^(q))), and we speak about this so: concerning equiva-

lence the family of infinite sets (as well as finite sets) divides on classes "to within an element".This result, obviously in turn, opens a new way of research a continuum-hypothesis [1]. We have written down below without the proofs only two of statements which of them is equivalent to Theorem 6 and they both as well as Theorems 1-6 are obvious to the finite sets.

Statement 1. If 5o4and фeI(A,B), then = ф.

Statement 2A ~ßo(ße, (В, B)~Bex {А, А)<(В {А, А) ~В (В, Л)).

The second part of the Statement 2, namely the equivalence

Bex(B,B)~Bex(A,A)« (.B(A,A)~B(B,A)),

characterizes the property for the equivalent sets to be indiscernible in the functional altitude.

Reference

1. CohenPaul J. Set theory and continuum hypothesis. - Princeton - New Jersey - Toronto -London - New York: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1966.

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

2. Mathematics dictionary. Edit. By Glenn James and Robert C. James.- D. van Nostrand company, 1958.

3. Halmos Paul R. Naive set theory. - Princeton- New York: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960.

4. Бурбаки Н. Теория множеств / пер. с франц. - Москва: Мир, 1965.

5. DieudonneJ. Foundations of modern analysis. Academic Press New York and London, 1960.

6. Сухотин А. М. Альтернативное начало высшей математики. Альтернативный анализ: обоснование, методология, теория и некоторые приложения. - Saarbrucken: LAPLambertAcade-micPublishingGmbH&Co. KG, 2011. - 176 c.

7. Hasse H. Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie. - Berlin, 1950.

8. Mendelson El. Introduction to mathematical logic. -New York: D. Van Nostrand Company,

1957.

9. Галилей Г. Избранные труды: в 2 т. - Москва: Наука, 1964. Т. 2.

10. Kleene S.C. Mathematical logic. -John Wiley&Sons,1967.

11. Euclid's "Elements": transl. from Greek .- М. ; -.L.: ОGIZ, 1948. Books I-VI (In Russian).

12. Kleene S.C. Introduction to metamathematics.- New York: D. van Nostrand company,1952.

13. KellyJ. General topology.- Princeton, New York: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1957.

УДК 621.331.221:681.526 (571.51)

ИСПОЛЬЗОВАНИЕ ОНТОЛОГИЧЕСКОГО ПОДХОДА В СИСТЕМЕ УПРАВЛЕНИЯ ИНТЕЛЛЕКТУАЛЬНЫМ КАПИТАЛОМ ОРГАНИЗАЦИИ

Вадим Германович Тарасов,аспирант Тел.: +7 923 2030840, e-mail: tarasovvg@mail.ru Сибирский государственный технологический университет http://www.sibstu.kts.ru

Описывается развитие информационной системы для автоматизации обслуживания и ремонта измерительных приборов и нагревающейся автоматики и измерения теплоэлектростанции Норильска. Особенность в использовании онтологического подхода к построению системы интеллектуальной поддержки. Согласно результатам экспериментального использования системы, удалось оценить рентабельность и возможные области для дальнейшего развития.

Ключевые слова: Обслуживание и Восстановление Оборудования, Система планирования ресурсов предприятия, Система Управления знаниями.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.