Научная статья на тему 'Physis in the Pythagorean tradition'

Physis in the Pythagorean tradition Текст научной статьи по специальности «Языкознание и литературоведение»

CC BY
267
53
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
Журнал
Philologia Classica
Scopus
ВАК
Ключевые слова
ФИЛОЛАЙ ИЗ КРОТОНА / PHILOLAUS OF CROTON / ARCHYTAS OF TARENT / ПИФАГОРЕЙСКАЯ ТРАДИЦИЯ / PYTHAGOREN TRADITION / PHYSIS / АРХИТ ИЗ ТАРЕНТА

Аннотация научной статьи по языкознанию и литературоведению, автор научной работы — Zhmud Leonid

This paper discusses the notion of physis in the fragments of the Pythagoreans Philolaus of Croton and Archytas of Tarentum. Building on the twentieth-century discussion of the two basic meanings of physis, ‘growth’ and ‘being’ (section 2), it argues that Philolaus was most probably the author of the first treatise entitled Περὶ φύσεως, as the first-century BC writer Diogenes of Magnesia testifies. The remaining evidence on Presocratic books entitled Περὶ φύσεως is late and unreliable (section 3). φύσις in Philolaus B 1 and 6 denotes ‘all that exists’; the Pythagorean speaks of physis in a generalized collective sense as of everything that came into being and exists in the world-order (section 4). As distinct from Philolaus, Archytas did not develop a doctrine of principles, and his epistemology was not constrained by metaphysical presuppositions. Archytas B 1 considers physis from both cosmological and epistemological points of views, as ‘the nature of the whole’ that is available to human cognition. Without setting any conditions or limitations to this process, as Philolaus did, he reinforces the latter’s declaration that “all the things that are known have number” (B 4) by making four Pythagorean mathēmata the principal cognitive tools for scientific enquiry into nature (section 5).

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.

Текст научной работы на тему «Physis in the Pythagorean tradition»

UDC 821.14+1

Philologia Classica. 2018. Vol. 13. Fasc. 1

Physis in the Pythagorean Tradition*

Leonid Zhmud

Institute for the History of Science and Technology, Russian Academy of the Sciences, 5, Universitetskaya nab., St. Petersburg, 199034, Russian Federation; l.zhmud@spbu.ru

For citation: Leonid Zhmud. Physis in the Pythagorean Tradition. Philologia Classica 2018, 13(1), 50-68. https://doi.org/10.21638/11701/spbu20.2018.104

This paper discusses the notion of physis in the fragments of the Pythagoreans Philolaus of Croton and Archytas of Tarentum. Building on the twentieth-century discussion of the two basic meanings of physis, 'growth' and 'being' (section 2), it argues that Philolaus was most probably the author of the first treatise entitled nspi q>uas«i, as the first-century BC writer Diogenes of Magnesia testifies. The remaining evidence on Presocratic books entitled nspi 9uas«i is late and unreliable (section 3). a ^uai^ in Philolaus B 1 and 6 denotes 'all that exists'; the Pythagorean speaks of physis in a generalized collective sense as of everything that came into being and exists in the world-order (section 4). As distinct from Philolaus, Archytas did not develop a doctrine of principles, and his epistemology was not constrained by metaphysical presuppositions. Archytas B 1 considers physis from both cosmological and epistemologi-cal points of views, as 'the nature of the whole' that is available to human cognition. Without setting any conditions or limitations to this process, as Philolaus did, he reinforces the latter's declaration that "all the things that are known have number" (B 4) by making four Pythagorean mathemata the principal cognitive tools for scientific enquiry into nature (section 5).

Keywords: Philolaus of Croton, Archytas of Tarent, Pythagoren tradition, physis.

1. The Ionians and the Pythagoreans

The Pythagorean arithmos has been frequently commented upon from the time of Aristotle (Metaphysics A), whereas the notion of physis in Pythagorean philosophies received much less attention. This is unfair, if only because in the preserved fragments of Philolaus and Archytas physis occurs no less often than arithmos and is no less significant: in both cases we can safely infer a new, comprehensive meaning of physis. Yet Philolaus' fragments have been long regarded as spurious,1 and Archytas until recently has not been considered a philosopher worthy of attention,2 so scholars writing on the notion of physis in the Presocratics as a rule associated it primarily with the Ionians and their nspi ^uaswc; latopia.3

The fact, however, is that the sixth-century Milesians were engaged in the inquiry into nature without knowing the formula nspi ^uaswc; laxopia that is first attested in Plato

* I would like to thank Luc Brisson for his kind invitation to the seminar "Platon et la tradition de Yhistoria peri phuseds" held on 26 May 2011 at the CNRS (Paris), where the first version of this paper was presented. I owe much to Gottfried Heinemann's (Kassel) constructive criticism that saved me from publishing a contradictory version of the present work.

1 Until Burkert 1972 (German original 1962) proved the authenticity of a part of them, B 1-7, 13.

2 Even after Huffman 2005, a major work on Archytas, he is still missing in Graham 2010.

3 Those who regarded Philolaus as spurious include e.g. Hardy 1884, 29-30; Heidel 1910, 97 n. 4, 111; Beardslee 1918, 14; Schmalzriedt 1970, 85 n. 7, but cf. 126 and n. 21; Kirk 1954, 230 n. 1.

© St. Petersburg State University, 2018

(Phd. 96a). Though our evidence on the Milesians is very meagre, the phrase nepl фиашс; never occurs in the fragments of the fifth-century Ionians Heraclitus, Anaxagoras, and Diogenes of Apollonia. Anaxagoras does not mention фшк; at all, while in Heraclitus and Diogenes it reveals a familiar notion of the particular 'nature' of an individual thing, not of 'nature' in general.4 This is also true for Parmenides and Empedocles, though in some cases they employed фШ1; in the sense of "birth", "origin".5 As for the Pythagoreans, it can hardly be a coincidence that Philolaus was the first Presocratic philosopher to use the formula nepl фшш; and that it occurs in Archytas as well; both of them discussed physis in a wide cosmological context. Besides, there is a good chance that Philolaus wrote the very first treatise entitled nepl фшеш;. The fragments of both Pythagoreans bear important witness to how the concept of physis has evolved in the Presocratic period and can shed light on the problem of when nepl фиаеш; became a generic title for the writings of the Presocratics. This also encourages us to take a fresh look at this topic.

2. Discussion of the meaning of фиац

By way of introduction, it is worth reminding ourselves of a discussion on the meaning of physis held in the previous century.6 Some scholars believed that the basic etymological meanings of фШ1;, "growth, origin, generation", derived from фиш/фшцш, is retained in the philosophical usage of the fifth century, whereas others denied or questioned this, insisting that "being, essence, nature" is the most usual meaning of the word. Thus, according to Frederick Woodbridge, the Presocratics meant under physis "birth," "origin," or "coming into being", so that the title nepl фшеш; has to be understood as On Origin, On Birth, On Coming into Being, On Growth. For the definition of nepl фшеш; laxopia he referred to Plato's middle dialogue Phaedo.7 The opposite opinion has been formulated by John Burnet in his influential Early Greek Philosophy: the original meaning of physis in the early Presocratics was 'primary substance', as in the passage in Plato's late dialogue Laws (891c). Accordingly, "the title nepl фuаeш;, so commonly given to philosophical works of the sixth and fifth centuries BC, means simply Concerning the Primary Substance"8 It turned out, then, that Plato would suit both interpretations.9

Burnet's view was energetically supported by Arthur Lovejoy: "...especially in the treatises of the cosmologists, фШ1; meant 'the intrinsic and permanent qualitative constitution of things' or, more colloquially, 'what things really are,' or, — with a slight modification of Burnet's translation, — 'the essential character of the primary substance'".10 On the contrary, William Heidel considered Burnet's interpretation too narrow; in a long and

4 Heraclitus B 1: ... okoiwv syw 6ir|yeu|iai ката yuaiv5iaipswv ёкаатоу ка! ypa^wv окшс ex£1; B 112: awypovsiv арет^ ц£у(атг|, ка! аоф(г| а\г|9£а Xsysiv ка! noisiv ката yuaiv ¿яаТоутац; B 123: yuaic 5е каб' 'Нрак\£1ТОУ криятеа9а1 yiXsi. Diogenes B 2: ... si toutov т1 |v sTCpov той Ётерои, sTCpov ov т| i6ia yuasi, Kal то айто eov iieTsnrnre яо\\ах&; Kal ETepoiouTo...

5 28 B 10, 16; 31 B 8, 63, 110. See Heinimann 1945, 89-92; Pohlenz 1953, 422 n. 1; Kahn 1960, 200201; Schmalzriedt 1970, 114-116; Bremer 1989, 245, in detail Heinemann 2012, 107-109; 113-119.

6 See useful overviews in Mannsperger 1969, 5-23 and Buchheim 1999, 7 n. 1.

7 Woodbridge 1901, 367. ¿уш yap, £фг|> & Ke^nc, v^c wv баицаатшс ¿яебищаа таитг|с тг|с ао-ф(ас ^v б^ ка\ойа1 яер! уиаешс iaTOpiqv- йя£pr|фаvоc yap |ioi ¿бока £Ьа1, аб^а! тас аМас ёкаатои, 6ia т( YÍYV£Таl EraaTOv ка! 6ia т( аяоМшш ка! 6ia т( ёат1 (96a6-10).

8 Burnet 1908, 12-13.

9 For the diversity of meanings of physis in Plato's dialogues, see Mannsperger 1969.

10 Lovejoy 1908, 376, cf. 383. See also Lovejoy 1910, 666.

learned article he decided to demonstrate that the primary meaning of puait;, "growth", is reflected in its philosophical usage as a "process", "the beginning or end of the process": "... as we have seen, while the inquiry or iaxopia nepi puaew; concerned the question 'what is it' (Ö ti ¿axi), the answer at once carried the inquirer to the further questions 'of what is it constituted' and 'how did it come about'".11 In his dissertation on the use of puai; in the fifth century John Beardslee did not find any instance when puai; can be translated as "element", noticing at the same time that the word had already lost its associations with puw and had come to mean 'nature': "When the puai; of an object is so spoken of, the whole nature of that object seems to be meant, its origin, its description, its manner of working, its effects. It is wrong to single out any one of these".12 Yet Burnet remained unimpressed by criticism; in an appendix to the third edition of his book he strongly questioned both that the original meaning of puai; is "growth" and, on a related point, that its semantic connection with puo^ai was still palpable.13

Further research wavered back and forth, though on a more sophisticated and comprehensive level, between positions already taken on, i.e. between "growth" and "being", two meanings already embedded in the Indo-European root *bheu-/*bhü-.14 Thus, Harald Patzer's brilliant study, submitted as a 1939 Habilitationschrift to Marburg University but published only half a century later, convincingly presented the history of the word puait; as an unfolding of the basic meaning of the verbal root pu-, "to grow", related to the plant world:

„.wie die Wurzel -yev- ursprünglich auf das eigentümlich tierische Hervorbringen oder Hervorgehen („gebären" oder „geboren werden") geht, so die Wurzel pu- auf das pflanzliche Hervorbringen oder Hervorgehen. Die Pflanze ist dementsprechend der gesuchte Urbereich der Wurzel pu-und das Hervorbringen oder Wachsen die in dieser Wurzel angesprochene Urerscheinung."15

On the contrary, the principal thesis of his learned opponent Douwe Holwerda was that the fundamental and etymological meaning of puai; is to eivai (copulative and existential); this word refers to "being" and "essence", not to "growth", so that very few examples of puai; = pueiv, pueaöai were relegated to the very end of Holwerda's dissertation.16 At the same time, he agreed with many particular interpretations of Patzer because the latter maintained that puai; means not the process of pueiv and pueaöai but its result: "puait; und pu| bedeuten also ein Sein, und zwar das sich im pueiv und pueaöai zur Erscheinung bringt und dadurch den ablösbaren Inhalt der Verben ausmacht".17 By the mid-century the double aspect of the root *bheu-/*bhü- has become generally accepted, and the discussion centred on which of them, dynamic or static, was decisive in the history of puai;.

11 Heidel 1910, 97; 129.

12 Beardslee 1918, 11; 65; 93.

13 Burnet 1920, 393-394.

14 Frisk 1970, 1052; Chantraine 1974, 1235; Beekes 2010, 1597: IE *bheh2u- 'grow, arise, be'. cpuo|iai in-tr. med. 'to grow, arise, spring up, become', perf. (and aor.) 'to exist or be endowed by nature, be there', trans. act. (factitive) 'to make grow, beget, bring forth' (Il.). cpuait; 'growth, character, descent, nature, being, etc.'

15 Patzer 1993, 12.

16 Holwerda 1955, 12; 108-109; 110-116. He approvingly cites Geoffrey Kirk: "Rather the truth is that at the 'primitive' stage of language there is no firm distinction between 'become' and 'be'. The root cpu- simply implies existence, and the broad general sense of cpuai;, from which all specialized senses are derived, is 'essence' or 'nature'" (Kirk 1954, 228).

17 Patzer 1993, 41.

Dietrich Mannsperger, for example, asserted that Patzer too closely related the noun фиак; to the verb фueаGаl, thus giving it too dynamic a character. He admitted, however, that Patzer represented the opinion dominant in German scholarship,18 whereas in English speaking countries Burnet's authority still stood in the background,19 and, one should add, no noteworthy general studies on the meaning of фиак; appeared since Beardslee.20

More consensus has been reached on another aspect of the concept of physis, namely, that it acquires its comprehensive meaning and becomes Allphysis, universal 'nature' and not 'nature' of something particular, in the last third of the fifth century. Respectively, a title nepl фuаeш;, where фиак; is used absolutely, without limiting genitive, becomes possible from this very period, when Philolaus' book was most probably published. Such a title is not safely attested earlier and if it were it would have meant something different. Already Heidel noted that early prose writings had no formal titles and that philosophical works bearing the title nepl фuаeш; appeared in the late fifth century.21 Although sporadic attempts to trace the history of this title up to Anaximander are still being made,22 they are not convincing.

3. Philolaus' title

Demetrius of Magnesia, a Hellenistic grammarian and librarian and acquaintance of Cicero, was first to mention the title of Philolaus' book in his bio-bibliographical work On Poets and Writers of the Same Name.23 According to Diogenes Laertius (8, 85 = 44 A 1), toutov (sc. Philolaus) ф^а1 ¿v 'O|wvti|oi; np^Tov ¿K6ouvai tov nuBayopiK^v

nepl фuaeш;, 6v apx^ а фиак; б' ¿v тф коацф .. .24 — "Philolaus was the first among the Pythagoreans to publish On Nature, the beginning of which is 'The nature in the world-order.'".25 Demetrius evidently had in his hands Philolaus' book, which he considered authentic (unlike Hippasus' spurious MuaTiKo; А.6уо;)26 and from which he, following the Alexandrian bibliographical tradition established by Callimachus, cited the first line. Demetrius was unaffected by the story that emerged in the late third century that Plato bought from Philolaus 'three Pythagorean books' published by him, containing the previously unavailable teaching of Pythagoras — the famous tripartitum.27 However, Hermann

18 See e.g. Diller 1939/1971, 145-147; Leisegang 1941, 1138; Heinimann 1945, 89; Pohlenz 1953, 422 n. 1, 426; Schmalzriedt 1970, 113-119; Bremer 1989, 242-243; Rechenauer 1991, 116-125; Buchheim 1999; Heinemann 2005, 19-21.

19 Mannsperger 1969, 19, cf. Buchheim 1999, 9-10. But see Kahn 1960, 201-202.

20 Naddaf 2005, translated from French, is derivative even when it is correct. See critical reviews: Mansfeld 1997; Schofield 2006.

21 Heidel 1910, 81 and n. 10. To this category he also related such Hippocratic writings as Пер! фйаешс; dv9pwnou, Пер! фйаешс; ncu5iou, etc.

22 See e.g. Rosetti 2006.

23 Demetrius' fragments are collected in Mejer 1981.

24 Reiske's conjecture <та' Пер! фйаеш; accounts for the plural wv and is accepted i.a. by M. Marcovich and T. Dorandi in their editions of Diogenes Laertius, but wv, as Burkert 1972, 241 n. 10 noted, does not necessarily mean that more than one book is intended. See also Huffman 1993, 93-94.

25 See also B 13 = Theol. Arithm. 25.18 de Falco, from Nicomachus: ФЛоХаос; ev тф Пер! фйаеш; Xeyei, and B 11 = Theon Smyrn. 106.10, from an unauthentic work: ФйоХаос; ev тф Пер! фйтшс;.

26 According to Sotion (D. L. 8,7), this was Hippasus' work, but Demetrius says that he left no writings (D. L. 8, 84). See Mejer 1981, 467-468.

27 D. L. 3, 9, cf. 8, 6. 9. 15: Мёхр1 Se ФйоХйои ойк |v ti yvwvai Пu9aY6рeюv боуца- оито; бе |6voc; ё^г^еуке та биар6г|та тр(а рфХ(а, а ПХйт^ ёяëaтelХev ёкатот |iva>v ^г|6г^а1; Aul. Gell. 3,17,1-5; Iamb.

Diels, who authored an excellent article on the pseudo-Pythagorean tripartitum,28 decided in his Vorsokratiker to relate this story to Demetrius' report and printed the following text: Philolaus npwxov ¿KÖoüvai xwv nuöayopiKwv <ßißX.ia Kai ¿rnypä^ai nepi> puaew;, wv apx^ ^5e (44 A 1). Diels' unsuccessful supplement greatly contributed to the popularity of the idea that Philolaus' book was the first written record of the Pythagorean doctrines and that he was the first Pythagorean to write a book.29 This obviously contradicts Demetrius' report stating that Philolaus was the first Pythagorean to publish a book entitled nepi puaew;, not that there were no books by the Pythagoreans before him. Indeed, we know of the books by Alcmaeon (24 B 1), Menestor (32 A 1-7), two works by Hippon (38 A 11), all of whom lived before Philolaus (no title for these writings is safely attested in the tradition). Demetrius, being a polyhistor (Dion. Hal. Din. 1), must have heard of them too. And of course, Philolaus' book contained not a 'Pythagorean dogma' (no all-Pythagorean philosophical teaching ever existed),30 but his own theories, which may or may not have coincided with the views of other Pythagoreans.

Demetrius is not an early author and yet his account on Philolaus' book is by far the first secure attestation of the title nepi puaew; for a Presocratic philosopher.31 The catalogue of Democritus' writings, compiled by Thrasyllus of Alexandria (died ca. 36 AD), contains about seventy titles one of which is nepi puaew; npwxov (D. L. 9, 46), but it is hard to say how authentic they are.32 All the other such titles appeared since the second century AD and/or do not look authentic: Rufus of Ephesus ap. Galen attests for Diogenes of Apollonia (64 B 9), Galen for Alcmaeon, Heraclitus, Parmenides, Emped-ocles, Melissus, Gorgias, Prodicus "and all the others" (24 A 2; 64 A 9; In Hipp. de nat. hom. XV, 5 Kühn), Sextus Empiricus again for Heraclitus (22 A 16), Parmenides (28 B 1), and Gorgias (82 B 3), Diogenes Laertius for Heraclitus (9, 5 = 22 B 1) and Empedo-cles (8, 77 = 31 B 1), Stobaeus for Xenophanes (21 A 36, B 30), Simplicius for Anaxagoras (59 B 4),33 Parmenides (28 A 14), Melissus (28 A 14, cf. 30 A 4), and Diogenes of Apollonia (64 A 4), the Suda (Hesychius) for Zeno of Elea (29 A 2).34 Something must have happened between ca. 50 BC, when Demetrius witnessed Philolaus' title, and ca. 170-190 AD, when Galen resolutely ascribed the title On Nature to writings of all the ancients.35

In the framework of this paper we leave open the question of what exactly has happened during this period. It should be stressed, however, that we cannot assume, as it is usually done, that the title nepi puaew; generally applied to the Presocratics' works

VP 199. See Zhmud 2012, 161-162.

28 Diels 1890/1969.

29 See e.g. Burkert 1972, 225 n. 35; Huffman 1993, 15.

30 Zhmud 2012, 109-111, 387-414.

31 'Liber de natura' in Cicero refers (pace Diels) to the subject of Metrodorus of Chios' book not to its title: is qui hunc [Democritus] maxime est admiratus, Chius Metrodorus, initio libri qui est de natura, 'nego' inquit, 'scire nos sciamusne aliquid an nihil sciamus...' (Acad. 11.23.73 = 70 B 1). For a useful overview of the evidence, see Heinemann 2011/2012, 205-212.

32 "Auf die Titel, die zudem oft variieren, ist kein Verlass", DK II, 130.7, cf. 68 B 5c: nepi puaew; a' üepi Koa|iou puaiw;>. Similarly Luria 1970, 410, 411 n. 13. The first list of Democritus' writings was

compiled by Callimachus.

33 But three other times Simplicius calls Anaxagoras' work OuaiKä (59 B 1, 16-17).

34 Themistius (Or. 35, p. 17 = 12 A 7) indicates the subject of Anaximander's book, not its title.

35 De elem. ex Hipp. I, 9: xa yap xwv naXaiwv änavxa nepi puaew; ¿•mysypa-nxai; cf. In Hipp. de nat. hom. I, 5: xoiauxa 5s eupoi; av änavxa xa üepi puaew; ¿niyeypa||£va ßißXia xwv naXaiwv piXoaopwv, 'E|ne5oK\£ou; Üap|evi5ou MeXiaaou AA_K|aiwvo; 'HpaKXeixou. Elsewhere Galen renders Prodicus' title as üepi puaew; dvGpwnou (De virt. phys. II, 9 = 84 B 4).

reflects the tradition of the third-century Alexandrian librarians.36 There is no firm evidence for this, and much of what we know about the Presocratic titles contradicts this assertion. Thus, the unanimous tradition from Aristotle (Mete. 382a1) to Simplicius calls Empedocles' physical poem Ouairn, whereas the stereotypic Пер! фиаеш; in Diogenes Laertius (8, 77, cf. 60) goes back to the title Пер! фшеш; tüv övtov given to this poem by Lobon of Argos (third century BC), notorious for his fabrications about Greek verse writers.37 This title is neither Empedoclean, nor Alexandrian. The only other Hellenistic evidence, that on Xenophanes' Пер! фиаеш; (21 B 30), derives from Crates of Mallus (mid-second century BC), a grammarian who worked in Pergamum (cf. 21 В 38, from Pollux). The very existence of such a poem by Xenophanes is highly doubtful.38

Egidius Schmalzriedt's study on the early history of the title Пер! фшеш; showed that it became possible only in the last quarter of the fifth century B. C., which matches with the history of the word фшк;.39 But his further conclusions that earlier the works of the Presocratics did not have any titles and that the generic title On Nature was given to all of them retrospectively in the Lyceum40 raise serious doubts. Indeed, the first Presocratic book titles appear in the generation of Empedocles and Ion of Chios, who were born around 490-485 BC, and conspicuously these titles were not Пер! фшеш;.41 Ion called his philosophical treatise Трюуцос; (36 A 1, B 2), and this unique word guarantees the authenticity of the title. One of Empedocles' poems is known in the manuscript tradition under the title Кабарцоц another as Ouairn. Leucippus' Меуа; бюкоацо; and Democri-tus' М1кро; бюкоацо; (D. L. 9, 46) were obviously entitled by the authors. Archytas' book titles were Äрцovlк6;, Пер! цабщатш^ Дютрфа!.42 What is decisive is that Schmalz-riedt didn't offer a single example that Aristotle, Theophrastus or other members of the Lyceum ever called a Presocratic book or, for that matter, any other book Пер! фшеш;. C. W. Müller noting this in his review suggested the Alexandrian library as the place where the scrolls of early Greek natural philosophers were inscribed Пер! фшеш;, in line with the terminology of the Lyceum (Aristotle often called them о1 пер! фшеш;).43 Theoretically this seems possible yet Müller also didn't attempt to substantiate his claim with any concrete evidence, whereas the material considered above strongly suggests a gap of more than 400 years between Callimachus' Pinakes and Galen's statement that writings of all the ancient philosophers were entitled Пер! фиаеш;. (Incidentally, it is more plausible that Galen became acquainted with these works in or via the library of his native Pergamum than in Alexandria.) Be that as it may, we do not find traces of a widespread Hellenistic custom originated in Alexandria to entitle the Presocratic books Пер! фиаеш;. Philolaus remains a special case, which increases the weight of Demetrius' report.

Admittedly, Demetrius' account in itself does not guarantee the authenticity of Philolaus' title but only that his book figured in the Alexandrian catalogue as Пер! фиаеш;.

36 Thus Schmalzriedt 1970, 111-112; Müller 1978, 631-632; Kirk, Raven, Schofield 1983, 101; Huffman 1993, 95.

37 31 A 1 (DK I, 282.15 and 33); Kroll 1922; Primavesi 2013, 680-682.

38 Schirren 2013, 342, 358-360.

39 See above, 52.

40 Schmalzriedt 1970, 83-107.

41 The fact that Ion was a dramatic poet and Empedocles wrote two poems in hexameter must have facilitated their decisions to name their works, for epic and dramatic poetry had titles long before.

42 47 B 1, 3, 4; cf. Huffman 2005, 30-32.

43 Müller 1978, 631-632.

Philolaus' title, however, is corroborated by two further facts. First, this is the opening of the treatise that introduces physis as its subject matter: a yuait; 8' ¿v tw Koa|w ap|6x6n aneipwv Te Kal nepaivovwv (B 1). Secondly, this is the formula nepl yuaewt;, where yuait; is used non-attributively: nepl 8e yuaio; Kal ap|ovia; Ö8e exei (B 6). It is in this fragment that aüxä |ev a yuait; becomes a subject of epistemological considerations. Both the combination of these features and each of them is unique for the Presocratic writings. Schmalzriedt conceded that among the Presocratics Philolaus alone may have written a book with a Titelersatz nepl yuaewt;, provided that the book is authentic and the fragment B 6, not B 1, opened it.44 But since he was not sure of either of these premises he treated Philolaus mostly in the footnotes, as a figure distorting his perspective. There is no need, however, to disprove Demetrius' report as "ein schlampiges Zitat", assuming that B 6 is more suitable as incipit than B 1.45 As Burkert aptly noticed, "a 8e in the first sentence, connecting it with the title, is found in several prose works of the fifth century (Her. B 1, Ion B 1); and this feature guarantees the title nepl yuaio;" that came after the author's name in the introductory sentence, for example, OiA.oA.aoq KpoTwvidTa; nepl yuaio; w8e Aeyei.46 Indeed, Schmalzriedt' view of the title as only a formal ¿nrypayl given by the author is too narrow for the fifth century BC; a thematic keyword or a clear indication of the subject matter in the opening sentence can easily fulfil the same function.47

To justify Philolaus' title some scholars cite as a parallel the title of Gorgias' treatise nepl xoü ^ övto; ^ nepl yuaewt; preserved by Sextus Empiricus (Adv. math. 7, 65 = 82 B 3). This is usually seen as a parody of Melissus' book nepl yuaewt; ^ nepl toü övTo;.48 Schmalzriedt took Gorgias' title as authentic but was indecisive about Melissus, for the latter does not fit his general conclusion that the formula nepl yuaewt; originated with the Sophists.49 But since Gorgias' title is hardly conceivable without that of Melissus, they stay or fall together, and there are plenty of reasons to regard them both as inauthen-tic, as Gottfried Heinemann persuasively argued.50 Gorgias' title is attested late, Melissus' very late; in neither case is there any certainty that they go back to the Hellenistic tradition of the Alexandrian library, let alone to their authors. To Galen both works were known as nepl ^uaew;, Olympiodorus also referred to Gorgias' treatise as nepl yuaewt; (In Plat. Gorg. p. 112 = 82 B 2), which makes it plausible that On Nature was in both cases an alternative title, not a part of the bipartite title. Now, Gorgias' treatise could well be called nepl Toü ^ övTo; either by the author or by readers, for this is his first and central argument,51 disregarding whether Melissus' book, against which it was allegedly directed, had a title nepl Toü övTo; (as the Suda reports: 30 A 2) or not (which is more plausible). Being is the main topic of Melissus, whereas yuait; in the Eleatic tradition belongs to the realm of becoming. Thus, it is hard to assume both that nepl yuaewt; first occurred as a part of the

44 Schmalzriedt 1970, 85 n. 7, 126.

45 Cf. Mansfeld 1997, 757 n. 2.

46 Burkert 1972, 252 and n. 68. Cf. Alcmaeon B 1 (below, 60, n. 70). Huffman 1993, 95 remarks that 8e "at best only guarantees some sort of introductory sentence".

47 Thus Müller 1978, 634. "Sieht man die Titelfrage unter sachlich-funktionalem Aspekt, so ist der Eingangssatz oder das Proöm Träger der Informationsfunktion des ,Titels', der in seiner verselbständigten späteren Form nicht selten der Themaangabe des Anfangssatzes entnommen ist" (ibid., 633).

48 Simpl. In Phys. 70.16; In De caelo 557.10 = 30 A 4. See e.g. Kirk, Raven, Schofield 1983, 102 n. 1; Huffman 1993, 95; Sedley 1999, 125.

49 Schmalzriedt 1970, 71-72, cf. 128. For criticism of this conclusion, see: Müller 1978, 630-631.

50 Heinemann 2011/2012, 209-212.

51 Tpia KaTä to E^rjt; KeydAaia KaTaaKeud(ei, sv |iev Kal npwTov öti oü8ev eaTiv (82 B 3).

composite title nspi puasw; ^ nspi xou ovxo;, or alternatively that Melissus followed an earlier work entitled nspi puasw;, for whose work could it be?52

4. ^uai^ in Philolaus

Moving from the authenticity of Philolaus' title to the meaning of puat; in B 1, let us quote it again in full:

a puai; 5' sv xw Koqaw ap|iox9r| s^ aroipwv te Kai nEpaivovTwv, Kai oAo; <o' Koa|o; Kai xa sv

auxW navxa.

"The nature in the world-order was constructed from unlimiteds and limiters, both <the> whole

world-order and everything in it." (Tr. D. Graham).

Philolaus opens his book with an emphatic a puat;, 'the nature in the world-order',53 which does not occur with an article in earlier philosophical texts, though often in dramatic poetry and history.54 In combination with an absolute usage of puat; (both are repeated in B 6: auxa |ev a puat;) this makes it an independent entity existing in the world-order and spatially limited by it (Sv xw Koa|w), and not the nature of something else. Heidel's suggestion to delete Sv and take puat; attributively with a Doric genitive, a Se puat; xw Koa|w = Koa|o;, is unnecessary and did not find much support;55 later he returned to the manuscript reading.56 If Philolaus' kosmos and everything in it was constructed, literally 'fitted together', from unlimited and limiting things, then the 'nature' in the kosmos designates all that this kosmos contains, the plenitude of what became and exists in it. This is picked up in B 2: S^Xov xapa oxi Sk nspaivovxwv xs Kai ansipwv o te Koa|o; Kai xa Sv auxw auvap|ox0n, which confirms that Philolaus distinguished between the kosmos as the world-order and (all) that has become and exists in it. Indeed, several commentators concur that under puat; in B 1 Philolaus meant 'all that exists', as Burkert renders it, "the totality of Sovxa".57 xa Sovxa, mentioned at the beginning of B 2 (avayKa xa Sovxa si|sv navxa ^ nspaivovxa ^ ansipa ^ nspaivovxa xs Kai ansipa) denote existing things, as in B 3 (navxwv Sovxwv) and again in B 6 (xa Sovxa Kai yryvwaKoisva up' a|wv), not elemental powers, as Huffman proposed,58 for there are not traces of such powers in Philolaus' text. Burkert refers to Holwerda, according to whom puat; is used here in its concrete collective sense and its meaning is close to that nav to ov.59 Holwerda,

52 Heinemann 2011/2012, 211-212.

53 "Durch den bestimmten Artikel erhält Physis einen besonders vollen und bedeutenden Klang; sie erscheint als selbständige Größe und Macht.. Besonders bezeichnend hierfür ist der Umstand, dass sie als regierendes Subjekt von Verben erscheint", notes Mannsperger 1969, 55 in respect to Plato.

54 Soph. Philoct. 873; Eur. Ion 642, fr. 264a Snell; Hdt. 3, 109; Thuc. 3, 64, 4.

55 Heidel 1907, 79; Beardslee 1918, 89; Nussbaum 1979, 94. Cf. Burkert 1972, 252 n. 58, who adduces parallels from Anaxagoras, xa ¿v xw svi Koa|iw (B 8), and Diogenes of Apollonia, xa ¿v xw5e xw KÖa|iw ¿ovxa (B 2); Huffman 1993, 99-100.

56 DK I, 407 not. According to Kranz, Diels "zweifelnd vermutete" a puai; <a> ¿v xw Koa|w, but this did not get into his text. Cf. Timapanaro Cardini 1961, 397 n.

57 Burkert 1972, 250 n. 58, 274.

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

58 Huffman 1993, 103-106.

59 Holwerda 1955, 78.

in turn, approvingly cites Patzer, who in the section devoted to фйак; as 'Art' or 'allgemeines Wesen, briefly comments on Philolaus B 1:

"A passage in Philolaus focuses on the content, explaining the necessary order of фйот;, <...>; коацо; denotes the ordered structure of the world, while фйак; is the entity filling this structure. Thus, physis is here not, as was up to this point usually the case, an abstract concept, but denotes in concrete fashion all things that have come into being (фйеабш in its wider sense) taken together in their entirety <...>. This shift in meaning can explain the later very common usage of фйот; as 'the being in its entirety', 'the universe, although then normally a qualifying adjective is added that hints at the universality of фйот;, like бХо;, па;. ."60

Carl Huffman in his fundamental study of Philolaus considered this understanding of physis mistaken. He suggested, with reference to Geoffrey Kirk and Charles Kahn, that фйа1; means here 'nature' or 'real constitution', adducing as a good parallel Heraclitus' famous dictum "фйак; loves to hide" (22 B 123).61 To this it should be objected that Kirk and Kahn discussed not Philolaus but Heraclitus, and if they (partially) agreed that фйак; in Heraclitus, who twice employs the locution ката фйагу (B 1, 112), means 'nature' or 'real constitution' of a thing or individual things (Kirk), or "the essential character of a thing as well as the process by which it arose" (Kahn),62 nothing suggests that this meaning would suit Philolaus, for his physis is universal, not particular, and denotes a collective whole arising in the process of cosmogony. Huffman's internal argument that if physis is "all that exists," then the sentence becomes intolerably repetitious, is again not convincing: the second part of the sentence, ка! бЛо; <o' коацо; ка! та ¿v аитф navTa, can be very well understood as an epexegetic apposition to the first part,63 where ка! та ¿v аитф п^та chiastycally refers to the фйак;.64

Philolaus' physis is not eternal. It comes into being in the process of the fitting together of two principles, unlimiteds and limiters, by harmonia (B 6). Philolaus nowhere explains what his principles are, but insists they are absolutely necessary for the formation of the world-order. Unlimiteds and limiters are eternal, they pre-exist the kosmos and the physis, which emerge from their interaction. The physis clearly demonstrates its coming to be, yet the cosmogonic process by which it arose is no more like organic growth. Due to the peculiar, rather abstract character of Philolaus' principles, differing from the organic elements and powers of earlier Presocratics, he repeatedly resorts to technological rather than organic metaphors: арцохбп (B 1), ашарцохбп (B 2), коац^б^ац аиукекЛ.£1а0а1 (B 6), то ap^oaGev (В 7).65 The first thing that emerged in the process of cosmogony, Hes-

60 Patzer 1993, 66-67, tr. Karla Pohlmann.

61 Huffman 1993, 96-97. See also Nussbaum 1979, 94-95: "real nature", "essence as revealed in process", but she followed Heidel 1907, 79 and took puai; xw Koa|iw as "the kosmos in its essential nature".

62 Kirk 1954, 42, 228-230; Kahn 1960, 201-202. In a footnote Kirk mentions that the meaning of puai; in Philolaus' B 1 and 6, which he considered spurious, "may be the same as for the Presocratics" (230 n. 1), that he believed was 'real constitution'. Unlike Kirk, Kahn stressed the dynamic character of physis.

63 Timpanaro Cardini, 1961, 397 n.; Nussbaum 1979, 94 n. 77. Philolaus' repetitiveness is notorious (Burkert 1972, 252).

64 His second internal argument (Huffman 1993, 97) is that in B 6 ^urn; is paired with "the being of things" as being beyond human knowledge and thus cannot mean "the totality of things". However, in the commentary to B 6 he insists that avra |i£v a ^urnc; is not the same puai; in the world-order as in B 1 (Huffman 1993, 125, 132-133), which, if true, undermines the validity of the original argument. See below, 59.

65 Empedocles employed ap^oZsiv and ap|iovia in regard to the process of mixing four elements (31 B 23, 71, 107).

tia (Central fire), was fitted together in the same way as the physis: to nparov ap|oaBev, to ev, ¿v tw |eaw raq a^aipaq earia KaXeirai (B 7). The very name of Hestia implies that it is made, not grown.

Fragment B 6 clarifies Philolaus' views of physis, especially of its knowability. Here it occurs twice, first at the very beginning of the fragment, which indicates the change of the topic: nepl Se ^uaioq Kal ap^oviaq wSe exei. To be sure, what follows is only partially new, for Philolaus insistently repeats things already said in B 1-2: everything in the world-order came into being from unlimiteds and limiters ordered by harmonia.

nepl Se yuaioq Kal ap|ioviaq «Se exei- a |isv ¿arw rwv npay^aTwv a'i'Sioq eaaa Kal aura |isv a yuaiq 0eiav -ya Kal ouk av6pwmvr|v ¿vSsxerai -yvwaiv nAav -ya ^ ori oux oiov r' ^v ouGevl rwv ¿ovrwv Kal -yryvwaKo|isv«v U9' a|iwv -ya -yevsaGai unapxouaaq raq ¿arouq rwv TCpa-y|iarwv, ¿^ wv auvsara 6 K6a|ioq, Kal rwv nepaivovrwv Kal rwv aneipwv. ¿nel Se ral apxal unapxov oux o|otai ouS' o|69u\oi eaaai, ^Sr| aSuvarov ^q Ka auraiq Koa|ir|6f|vai, e'l ap|ovia ¿ne-ysvero wriviwv aSe rponwi ¿-ysvero. ra |isv wv 6|ioia Kal o|69u\a ap|oviaq ouSev ¿neSsovro, ra Se avo|oia |nSe o^oyuXa |ir|S£ t iaoraxrj avayKa ra roiaura ap|iovia auyKeKXeiaGai, oi'ai |isAAovri ¿v Koa^wi KarsxeaGai.

"Concerning nature and harmony the situation is this: (1) the being of things, which is eternal, and nature itself admit of divine and not human knowledge, except that it was impossible for any of the things that are and are known by us to have come to be, if the being of the things from which the cosmos came together, both the limiters and the unlimiteds, did not preexist. (2) But since these beginnings preexisted and were not alike nor even related, it would have been impossible for them to be ordered, if a harmony had not come upon them, in whatever way it came to be. Like things and related things did not in addition require any harmony, things that are unlike and not even related nor of [? the same speed], it is necessary that such things be bonded together by this kind of harmony, if they are going to be held in an order."66

Having promised to explain ^uaiq and ap^ovia which occur again, respectively, in the first and the second part of his argument, Philolaus introduces a new concept, the being of things (a |ev ¿arw rwv npayiarwv), that also needs explication. In a manner typical of post-Eleatic ontology, he distinguishes between eternal (a'i'Sioq) being and preexisting principles, on the one hand, and generated things, such as the kosmos and ra ¿ovra Kal YiyvwaK6|eva U9' a|«v, on the other. Where does aura |ev a ^uaiq (again used absolutely) belong? If this is the same physis as in B 1, which is conceived as the totality of ¿ovra comprising ra ¿v aurw (navra) (B 1-2), then it must belong to the realm of generated things, the more so as a'i'Sioq eaaa distinctly refers only to the being of things, not to the physis. Unlike other commentators, who treat physis in B 1 and B 6 as one and the same concept, Huffman takes "physis in the cosmos" (B 1) and "physis in itself" (B 6) as two different kinds of physis referring to different levels of reality. "Nature in itself", which is paired with eternal being, relates not to the "things in the natural world themselves, but rather to the ultimate reality or being that underlies the world-order".67

It is true that both eternal being and aura |ev a ^uaiq admit only of divine knowledge, but does it follow that Philolaus "discusses nature (^uaiq) in the sense of 'being'

66 I reproduce Huffman's text and translation, except for "nature in itself" in the second line (see below, 59) and ta roiaûra âp|iovia in the penultimate line. âp|iovia figuring in fragment B 6a is not a cosmic principle, but a musical interval octave, so that to roiaûra âp^ovia implies a different âp^ovia.

67 Huffman 1993, 125-127; 132-133.

(eaxw)", thus assimilating it to the ultimate reality?68 Philolaus' words remind us of the opening of Alcmaeon's treatise that was certainly known to him:69 "Of things invisible, as of mortal things, the gods have certain knowledge; but to us, as men, (only) inference from evidence (is possible)...".70 The closeness of their epistemological positions is obvious: for Alcmaeon certain knowledge of things both unseen and mortal is available only to the gods, for Philolaus both the eternal being of things and perishable physis admit only divine knowledge. Therefore, there is no need either to postulate two different kinds of physis or to duplicate a |ev ¿ax« xwv npay|dxwv by putting "essential nature" next to it, for being of things is the essence of npay|dxwv. By xa npdy|axa both times not the ordinary things (xa ¿v auxw navxa, xa ¿ovxa) are meant, but their constituents, ansipa and nspaivovxa. Although aura |ev a puat; shares with the being of things one epistemological attribute, being (fully) available only to the gods, this does not make it the Kantian 'Ding an sich', as Nussbaum thought.71 It is the same physis as in B 1, only emphatically underlined: "and the physis itself", "and the very physis".72

What Philolaus wanted to say was that the physis itself, that is the totality of ¿ovxa, is available for human cognition only under certain conditions, which are partly ontologi-cal, partly epistemological. First, we are to recognize that no existing and knowable things would have come into being if a) the being of the principles did not preexist and b) these opposing principles were not fitted together by harmonia. Secondly, none of all existing things (ndvxwv ¿ovxwv) would have been knowable, if they were only unlimiteds: apxav yap ouSe to yvwaou^svov ¿aastxai ndvxwv ansipwv ¿ovxwv — "There will be nothing knowable at all, if all things are unlimited" (B 3).73 B 3 seemed to serve as a link between Philolaus' epistemology and ontology; partly repeating what has been already said in B 1-2, it adduced an additional argument from cognition. Thirdly, existing things are known to us to the extent that they have number, that is, are countable, measurable, etc.:

Kai navxa -ya |av xa -yryv«aKO|isva api0|6v sxovxi- ou -yap oxiwv <oiov' te ouSev ours vor|6f||Ev ours -yvwa0fj|isv avsu rourou.

"And indeed all the things that are known have number. For it is not possible that anything whatsoever be understood or known without this" (B 4, tr. C. Huffman).

68 Huffman 1993, 126, 131.

69 For Alcmaeon's influence on Philolaus, see Zhmud 2012, 367, 389-390, 393.

70 ÄA.K|aiwv Kpoxwvirxn; xä5e sXe^e Üeipi9ou uic; Bpoxivwi Kai Asovxi Kai Ba9uAAwi- nepi xwv äpavswv, nepi xwv 9vr|xwv aap|veiav |Sv 9eoi sxovxi, w; 5s dv9p«noit; xeK|iaipea9ai Kai xa ¿ä;fjc; (D. L. 8, 83 = 24 B 1, tr. R. Hicks, the parentheses are mine). Huffman 1993, 126 mentions only "things unseen", leaving out "mortal things", which gives a very different sense to the fragment. Before Diels scholars like Zeller, Cobet and Gomperz considered nepi xwv 9vr|xwv an interpolation, but after his Vorsokratiker ("Alkmaion gibt gleich am Anfang sein Thema an, er handelt sowohl über dpavf wie über 9vr|xä, DK I, 214 not.) overwhelming majority of scholars accepted the manuscript reading. Gemelli Marciano 2007, 18-22, gives a different meaning to nepi xwv 9vr|xwv.

71 Nussbaum 1979, 102.

72 Thus Graham 2010, 493: "... the essence of things, being eternal, and nature itself admit of divine but not human knowledge"; Laks, Most 2016, 157, D5: "... the being of things, which is eternal, and nature itself admit knowledge that is divine and not human".

73 For to yvwaou|ievov, see Timpanaro Cardini 1961, 402; Huffman 1993, 116-120; Zhmud 2012, 402 n. 58.

Obviously, not ra ¿ovra navra are yryvwaKoieva by us: among existing things there are those which are unlimited and do not possess number; consequently, the 'nature' in its totality is not available to human knowledge.

The proclaimed epistemic modesty did not impede Philolaus to write a treatise, where he in a manner already traditional for the Presocratics proceeds from cosmogony and cosmology to physiology and medicine. Incidentally, he and his fellow Pythagorean Hippon are the only Presocratics, whose theories of medicine are outlined by the Peripatetic Menon in his medical doxography.74 It is the conventional dualistic conception of Ionian study nepl ^uaewq vs. Pythagorean number metaphysics that still hinders recognizing Philolaus as the first philosopher who took physis as the main subject of his treatise. Meanwhile, even Aristotle admitted that the Pythagoreans, that is in the first place Philolaus, Koa|onoiotiai Kal ^uaiKwq pouXovrai Aiyeiv (Met. 1091a20-21). Let us briefly recapitulate what is known about the physis from Philolaus' fragments.75 He employs ^uaiq absolutely and speaks of it in a generalized collective sense as of everything that came into being and exists in the world-order (ra ¿v aurw navra). The physis is the entity generated or constructed from eternal limiters and unlimiteds fitted together by harmonia; to understand it one needs to know the way it arose. Philolaus shared with contemporary thought this dynamic perception of ^uaiq, whether general, as in the famous fragment of Euripides, "Blessed is he. who contemplates the ageless order of immortal nature, how it is constituted and when and why",76 in the Dissoi logoi,77 and Xenophon's Memorabilia,78 or particular, as human physis in the Hippocratic corpus.79 Unlike "the ageless order of immortal nature" in Euripides, a'i'Sioq in Philolaus is reserved only for the 'being of things'.80 Since limiters, unlimiteds, and harmonia are not like organic elements and forces, the coming to be of the physis is described in technological terms, though the verb yeveaBai is employed as well. The physis in Philolaus is passive, it does not figure as the subject of the active verbs, at least not in the preserved material. Finaly, the 'nature' as the totality of ¿ovra admits only divine knowledge, and for human cognition it is available only under certain conditions set out in Philolaus' book.

5. ^ugi^ in Archytas

An important source of Philolaus' epistemology were the exact sciences, the successes of which made highly attractive the methods of cognition adopted in them. Familiar with all the sciences of the Pythagorean mathematical quadrivium,81 Philolaus became the first

74 Huffman 1993, 289-306.

75 Cf. Heinemann 2011/2012, 134-140.

76 öAßio; öaTi; Trjt; iaTopia; eaxe |id9r|aiv, ||Te noArrwv ¿nl nr||ioauvr|v ||t' ei; a8iKou; npd^ei; op|wv, äAA' dSavdTou Ka9op«v yuaew; Koa|iov dy|p«v, nrj Te auveaTr| Kal ornr Kal onwc (Eur. fr. 910).

77 ... Kal nepl yuaio; twv andvTwv w; Te exei Kal w; ¿ysveTo, 8i8daKev (Dialex. 8).

78 oi>8e yäp nepl Trj; twv ndvTwv yuaew;, flnep twv aAAwv o'l nAeiaToi, 8ieAsyeTo aKonwv on«; o KaAou|ievo; üno twv aoyiaTwv Koa|o; exei Kal Tiaiv avdyKai; SKaaTa yiyveTai twv oupaviwv (Mem. 1, 1, 11).

79 Teivei 8e airreoiaiv o Aoyo; ¿; yiAoaoyir|v, KaSdnep'E|ine8oKAfjc; ^ aAAoi o'l nepl yuaio; yeypdyaaiv ¿^ äpxn; ö Ti ¿aTiv avSpwno;, Kal on«; ¿ysveTo npwTov Kal on«; ^uvendyr| (De vet. med. 20). ®r||i 8e 8eiv Tov |sAAovTa op9w; ^uyypdyeiv nepl 8iaiTn; avSpwnivn; npwTov |iev navTo; yuaiv avSpwnou yvwvai Kal 8iayvwvai^ yvwvai |iev äno Tivwv auvsaTr|Kev ¿2; äpxfj; (De victu 1, 2).

80 For the destruction of the world, see A 18.

81 Geometry (A 7a), arithmetic (A 13, B 4-5), astronomy (A 16-22, B 7), harmonics (B 6a).

Pythagorean and one of the first Presocratics to introduce mathemata into a philosophical work and make its results and methods an object of discussion. This line was continued by his younger contemporary Archytas, an original thinker, brilliant mathematician and successful politician, seven times elected strategos in his native city. According to Eude-mus of Rhodes' History of Geometry (fr. 133 Wehrli), Archytas was Plato's coeval, perhaps somewhat older than him, since Archytas' influence on Plato can be traced, but not the reverse.82 He is mentioned in the Seventh Letter (350a) as a politician who helped Plato return from Syracuse, where he had been detained by Dionysius the Younger. Though Archytas does not figure in the Platonic dialogues, there is a reference to his work in the Republic,83 and generally we can safely regard him as the author of the idea, so precious to Plato, of the beneficial effect of mathematics on the soul and thus on society. In the introduction to nspi |a0n|drwv (B 3), Archytas relates to the discovery of calculation such important social changes as an increase of concord and an advance toward greater equality. Moreover, calculation proves capable of improving people's moral qualities, keeping them from greed and injustice or, at any rate, exposing these vices.84

As distinct from Philolaus, Archytas did not develop a doctrine of principles, and his epistemology was not constrained by metaphysical presuppositions. His philosophy, preserved very badly, looks rather like the philosophy of a scientist and a mathematician of the age of the Sophists. Archytas starts his Harmonics by praising his predecessors, ol nspi xa |a0^|ara, that is those concerned with astronomy, geometry, arithmetic, and harmonics, for their, one might say, great epistemological successes:

KaXw; |oi Sokouvti roi nspi xa |ia0^|iara Sia-yvwvai, Kai ou0ev aronov op0w; autoi; old ¿vri, nspi eKdarwv 0swpstv- nspi -yap xa; rwv oXwv puaio; KaXw; Sia-yvovrs; E|isAAov Kai nspi rwv Kara |ispo; old ¿vri, oysta0ai. nspi te xa; rwv aarpwv raxuraro; Kai ¿niroXav Kai Suaiwv napsSwKav a|iv <aapf> Sid-yvwaiv Kai nspi -ya|iSTpia; Kai api0|wv Kai oux ^Kiara nspi |waiKa;. raura yap xa |ia0^|iara Sokouvti ^|ev aSsA-pEd.

"Those who concern themselves with the mathematical sciences seem to me to make distinction well, and it is not surprising that they think correctly, about each thing, how they are. For since they make distinctions well about the nature of the whole, they ought also to see well, about particular things, how they are. And certainly, about the speed of the heavenly bodies, their risings and settings, they have transmitted to us a clear distinction, and so too about geometry and numbers, and especially about music. For these sciences seem to be sisters."85

In his study of Archytas, Huffman argues that ol nspi xa |a0^|ara include both Pythagoreans and non-Pythagoreans such as Hippocrates of Chios.86 The problem is that arithmetic and mathematical harmonics up to the very end of the fifth century remained a monopoly of the Pythagorean school; Hippocrates and other Ionian mathematicians did not study them, hence ol nspi xa |a0^|ara refers to Archytas' Pythagorean predecessors, who like Hippasus, Theodorus of Cyrene or Philolaus, dealt with the sciences of the

82 Zhmud 2006, 92-94.

83 Astronomy and harmonics are kindred sciences, as the Pythagoreans say, and we agree with them (Res. 530d), which corresponds to Archytas B 1.

84 Zhmud 2006, 71-72, 110.

85 Archytas D 14 Laks-Most = 48 B 1, tr. Laks-Most. Unlike Huffman, who retains aapf omitted by Porphyry, Laks and Most print Porphyry's text but translate "clear distinction".

86 Huffman 2005, 52.

quadrivium.87 In his opinion, they showed true insight (raXwq Siayvwvai), and it is not strange that they have a correct understanding about particular things as they are. This is unusual for the Presocratic philosophers, who are known for their exceedingly critical attitude towards their predecessors, but Archytas was not a typical philosopher, and the Harmonics was not a philosophical treatise. Reliance on predecessors is essential for the scientific tradition, even if scientists do not state it as openly and generously as Archytas.88

It is in this context that yuaiq appears in the Harmonics. Right at the beginning Ar-chytas makes an important epistemological point: knowledge of particular things, such as the speed of the heavenly bodies or the pitch of the sound, depends on knowledge of the nature of the whole. If we take ^ rwv oXwv yuaiq as near equivalent to ^ rwv anavrwv yuaiq, or to ^ roti oXou yuaiq, for neutrum pluralis in Greek often substitutes collective notions, then Archytas meant by it the 'nature of the universe' or the 'nature as a whole' (cf. oXoq <o' Koa|oq in Philolaus B 1). In difference from to nav, to oXov (ra oXa)89 "designates not so much the all in its entirety as that which opposes all the partial experiences and embraces them";90 in our case, the latter are the discoveries made in each science. ^ yuaiq in this sense is the synonym and equivalent of to oXov, which with 6 Koa|oq was a common designation of universal nature viewed as a whole. Thus, the author of the Dis-soi logoi, where the Pythagoreans and Anaxagoreans figured as teachers of wisdom and virtue (DK 90, 6), tried to persuade his audience that an accomplished ao^iar^q, who knows nepl yuaioq rwv anavrwv 6q re exei Kal 6q ¿yevero, will be able to act rightly in regard to everything (8).91 Xenophon denied that Socrates had spoken nepl r^q rwv navrwv yuaewq, aKonwv onwq 6 KaXou|evoq uno rwv aoyiarwv Koa|oq exei (Mem. I, 1, 11).92 Plato mentions in the Lysis ol nepl yuaewq re Kal roti oXou SiaXeyo^evoi Kal ypayovreq (214b5) and in the Phaedrus Phaedrus answers Socrates' question "is it possible to reach a serious understanding of the nature of the soul without understanding the nature of the world as a whole" (r^q roti oXou yuaewq)93 that, according to the Asclepiad Hippocrates, we will not understand even the body without this method (270c).

Indeed, in the Hippocratic Corpus correct knowledge of diseases or of the diet is often made dependent on the knowledge of the entire human physis or of physis in general. Thus, in On Regimen, the most philosophically influenced treatise of the Corpus, we read: "I maintain that he who aspires to treat correctly of human regimen must first acquire knowledge and discernment of the nature of man in general" (navroq yuaiv avBpwnou yvwvai Kal Siayvwvai), including his original constitution (r^v ¿^ apx^q auaraaiv).94 In the same section the whole universe (oXoq 6 Koa|oq) appears among the factors considered by a doctor (I, 2), while further on it is stated that the human body is formed by imitation of the universe, ano|i|naiv roti oXou (I, 10). The author of the Epidemics also goes

87 Hippasus: 18 A 4, 12-15; Theodorus: 43 A 2-5; Philolaus: see above, 60, n. 81.

88 Cf. [Hipp.] De victu 1, 2.

89 For oXa see, e.g.: auXXa^ieq oXa Kal oux ®Xa, auiyepo^evov Siayepo^evov, auvaiSov SiaiSov, ¿k navrwv ev Kal ¿^ evoq navra (Her. fr. 25 Marcovich = 22 B 10 DK); ¿k rwv oXwv |iepea Siaipeerai, Kal ¿k rwv |epewv auvriBe|evwv oXa yiverai ([Hipp.] De victu 1, 6, see also 15, 17); Xen. Cyr. 8, 1, 13.

90 Bollack 1969, 14 n. 1.

91 On "the nature of the universe", see Robinson 1979, 224-225.

92 Cf. EwKparouq Se nepl |ev ra r|BiKa npay|areuo||evou nepl Se rrjq oXr|q yuaewq ouBev (Arist. Met. 987b2).

93 Tr. A. Nehamas. It is disputable whether to oXov means "the whole world" or "the whole question", see e.g. Joly 1961; Lloyd 1975/1991, 200-203. I prefer the first variant.

94 De victu 1, 2, tr. W. H. S. Jones.

beyond human physis: "The following were the circumstances attending the diseases, from which I framed my judgments (¿£ 6v бюугу^ако^), learning from the general nature of all and the particular nature of the individual", which, inter alia, includes learning "from the constitution, both as a whole and with respect to the parts, of the weather and of each region" (¿к т^; катаатааю; бЛ^;, ка! ката цереа tov oйpаvíшv ка! х^РП^ ёкаат^;).95 The Ancient Medicine famously criticises those doctors and philosophers who assert "that it is impossible for anyone to know medicine who does not know what the human being is. Their account tends towards philosophy, just like Empedocles or others who have written about nature from the beginning".96 Denying this philosophical approach, the author, however, claims that knowledge of human physis can be acquired only "when one has correctly grasped medicine itself in its entirety" (аитег^ ^v i^pt^v паааv). In view of these passages in philosophical and medical literature of Archytas' time, his idea that correct understanding of particular things achieved in particular sciences depends on good knowledge of the physis as a whole looks widely accepted. Regrettably, he does not say what this latter knowledge consists of, so we can only make informed guesses about it.

One would expect that speaking of cognition Archytas would employ the verbs ¿п£атацац as in his discussion of the cognitive method in B 3, or угу^акш, as in Philolaus B 4 and 6, but his central epistemological term, as Huffman notes, is бюу^шакш, "to discern, to distinguish"; it occurs three times in five lines.97 Interestingly, the closest parallel to this is found not in a philosophical text, but in two above quoted passages from On Regimen and Epidemics that deal with physis. Especially often бюугу^акш occurs in On Regimen, where it is employed alternatively and interchangeably with угу^акш.98 The same can be seen in Archytas B 1. When further on he speaks about bodies in motion which produce sounds, he again mentions physis, this time a particular human nature, and uses угу^акш in the sense "to discern, to recognize, to perceive":

Many of these sounds are not capable of being discerned by our nature (оик еЬа1 a|iwv та фйае! оюи; те угушакеабаО, some because of the weakness of the impact, some because of the extent of their distance from us, and some even because of their excessively great magnitude.99

Thus, my impression is that praising the great advances in knowledge Archytas emphatically used бюугу^акш to strengthen the potential of the root yvш- rather than to limit it to mere discernment or distinguishing between things.

95 Epid. I, 23, tr. W. H. S. Jones. See also De carn. 1.

96 De vet. med. 20, tr. M. Schiefsky.

97 Huffman 2005, 151.

98 1) ®r||i SS Ssiv tov |isAAovTa 6p9«c; ^uyypdpsiv nspi Siairr|c; dv9pwmvr|c; npwrov |Sv navroc; puaiv dv9p«nou yv^vai Kai Siayvoivai- yvwvai |Sv dno rivwv auv£arr|Ksv äpxfj;, Suayvävai SS uro rivwv |£pwv K£Kpcar|Tai- ei rs yap r^v e^ äpxfj; auaraaiv yv^asrai, dSuvaro; Sarai ra ün' ¿Ksivwv yiyv6|eva yv^vai^ ei Ts yv^asrai (<Sia>yvwa£tai: Joly) ro eniKpareov ev rw aw|ari, oüx iKavo; Sarai ra ^uipspovra rw äv9pwnw npoasvsYKsiv (1, 2, 122.22-26 Joly). 2) Asi Ss, w; SoiKs, rwv novwv SuayivwaKsiv r^v Suva|iiv... Aarpwv rs eniroXa; Kai Suaia; YivwaKsiv Ssi ... Taura SS ndvra SiaYvovri ouk« aurapKs; ro supn|ä eariv (1, 2, 124.9-10. 14-17). 3) ... e^ wv SuayivwaKsiv xp^ ^uXP^v puaiv Kai ÜYp|v (1, 32, 148.22); .roiaSs YivwaKsiv ÜYP^v Kai 9sp|^v puaiv (1, 32, 148.28-29). 4) sirs Yap r^v e^ äpxfj; auaraaiv

YvWasrai, dSuvaro; Sarai ra ün' eKsivwv Y^vö^sva Yvwvai (1, 2, 122.25-27). nspi |Sv ouv puaio; Suayvwaioc ourw xPH SiaYivwaKsiv rrjc; e^ äpxfj; ^uaraaio; (1, 32, 150.9-10). 5) SuayivwaKsiv (2, 37, 158.1); YivwaKsiv (2, 39, 162.9-10). Cf. Index Hippocraticus: Suay^vwaK« discerno, cognosco; SidYvwai; cognitio (Kühn, Fleischer 1989, 171).

99 Tr. A. Barker. Cf. also oü |ovov SS Ka rourwi Yvoirnsv (B 1, l. 41)

A different interpretation of the beginning of B 1 was suggested by Huffman. Since Archytas refers to "wholes" in the plural (rwv oXwv) rather to the "whole" in the singular, he does not mean the whole universe and its parts. These "wholes" are "the universal concepts of the given science", which is to say of astronomy or harmonics, and since they are carefully distinguished and defined by ol nepl ra |aB^|ara, scientists are "also able to understand the particular objects considered by the science".100 Thus, the fundamental concept ("the whole") in harmonics is sound, and it is precisely from sound that his predecessors began; in astronomy such a concept is 'motion'. "Archytas is arguing that those concerned with the sciences are good at making distinctions, because making distinctions is a central activity of the sciences".101 This account makes Archytas a true logician and a predecessor of Aristotle, whose distinction between the universal (KaBoXou) and particular (Kara |epoq) may have been, as Huffman believes, in part influenced by passages like Archytas B 1.

I do not find this interpretation convincing.102 First, I do not think there is much difference between yuaiq rwv oXwv and yuaiq roti oXou. As Holwerda noted, expressions such as ^ rwv oXwv (or rwv au|navrwv) yuaiq often appear in the texts, normally referring to the whole nature or to the universe in general, as, for example, in Epicurus or Zeno of Citium.103 Xenophon uses r^v rwv oXwv ra^iv in the similar meaning (Cyr. 8, 7, 22). Secondly, though Archytas developed a kind of philosophy of science, there is nothing like a definition of "the universal concepts of the given science" in it. In the introduction to nepl |aBn|arwv, where he lays out the major methodological principles of the sciences, no mention of 'making distinctions' is made. The key notions here denoting principal activities of the sciences in acquiring knowledge are |aGnaiq, Z^r^aiq and eupeaiq:

"For it is necessary to arrive at knowing what you did not know either by learning it from someone else or by discovering it yourself. Now what one learns from someone else also belongs to another, while what one discovers oneself belongs to oneself as one's own. But to discover without seeking is difficult and rare, while to do so by seeking is practicable and easy; but if one does not know (how) to seek, then to seek is impossible" (B 3).104

The independent discovery of new knowledge, says Archytas, is certainly preferable to learning from others, but to make such a discovery, and not an accidental find, a conscious search is needed, because one cannot research without knowing the method of research.105 This reminds us of the argument made in B 1: to be effective in search of particular truths one needs to know something more general.

In Archytas' view, both the universe in general and individual things are open to human cognition. Without setting any conditions or limitations to this process, as Philolaus

100 Huffman 2005, 57-68, 149-152.

101 Huffman 2005, 59.

102 For its criticism, see Barker 2006, 302-308, 315-318.

103 Holwerda 1955, 73. Tatira aoi, w HpoSore, eari KeyaXaiwSearara unep rfq tov oXwv yuaewq ¿nireT|n|eva (Epic. Ep. ad Her. 82); ri ouv ¿ari Beoq Kal ri yavraaia, Kal ri ¿ari yuaiq ^ ¿nl |epouq Kal ri ¿ari yuaiq ^ tov oXwv (Zeno fr. 182 SVF).

104 Tr. Laks-Most, slightly modified. Cf. Huffman 2005, 182-200; Zhmud 2006, 64-65; Barker 2006,

313.

105 Cf. De vet. med. 2 on method of research: "But anyone who casts off and rejects all these things (i.e. previous discoveries), tries to investigate in another way and another manner, and says that he has discovered something, has been deceived and continues to deceive himself: for this is impossible" (tr. M. Schiefsky).

did, he reinforces the latter's declaration that "all the things that are known have number" (B 4) by making four mathèmata the principal cognitive tools for scientific enquiry into nature. This is not exactly the nepl yuaeœ; laxopia that we, following Plato and Aristotle, used to associate with the Presocratics. Archytas' ol nepl xà ^aôr^axa, having appeared earlier than Aristotle's ol nepl yuaeœ;,106 partly overlap with them, as astronomy and harmonics are based on an empirical foundation and deal with physical reality. We do not know, how, and if, Archytas perceived the difference between the sister sciences, yet he obviously did not know of Platonic division into intelligible and sensible reality. His astronomy is concerned with the motion of the visible heavenly bodies, not with the ideal kinematics of mathematical heavens, as Plato wanted it to have (Res. 529a-530c). According to Archytas, ol nepl xà ^aGr^axa have already reached a correct understanding of these things and of nature as a whole, they did not need any intermediary to interpret the results of their scientific research. Plato, for his part, asserts that since the geometers and astronomers do not know how to make use of their discoveries, those of them who are not utter blockheads must hand these discoveries over to the dialecticians, who will find proper use for them (Euthyd. 290c). Does this not sound like a polemic with Archytas? Archytas' harmonic theory, Barker noted, "provides the impressions we receive in our musical experience with an intelligible basis in the world accessible to the quantifications and measurements of a physicist. [R]ather few of his successors seem to have followed him; most of them reverted to a more abstract approach, detached from the phenomena of musical experience. and heavily influenced by Plato".107 Plato's reaction to Archytas' theory is well known: the true science of harmonics must measure mathematical and not audible consonances, which is exactly what the Pythagoreans fail to realize (Res. 531c). The fruitfulness of Archytas' approach was fully appreciated only in early modern science, with a growing awareness that the book of Nature is written in the language of mathematics (Galileo Galilei).

Bibliography

Barker A. Archytas Unbound: A Discussion of Carl A. Huffman, Archytas of Tarentum. Oxford Studies in

Ancient Philosophy. 2006, 31, 297-321. Barker A. The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Beardslee J. W. The Use of yuan; in Fifth-Century Greek Literature (Diss.). Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, 1918.

Beekes R. Etymological Dictionary of Greek. Leiden, Boston, Brill, 2010. Bollack J. Empedocles. III. Les Origines: Commentaire 1. Paris, Les Éditions de Minuit, 1969. Bremer D. Von der Physis zur Natur. Eine griechische Konzeption und ihr Schicksal. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 1989, 43, 241-264. Buchheim T. Vergängliches Werden und sich bildende Form: Überlegungen zum frühgriechischen Naturbegriff. Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 1999, 41, 7-34. Burkert W. Lore and Science in AncientPythagoreanism. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1972. Burnet J. Early Greek Philosophy. London, A. & C. Black, 21908. Burnet J. Early Greek Philosophy. London, A. & C. Black, 31920.

Chantraine P. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque. Vol. 3. Paris, C. Klincksieck, 1974. Diels H. Ein gefälschtes Pythagorasbuch. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 1890, 3, 451-72 = Diels H. Kleine Schriften zur Geschichte der antiken Philosophie. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1969, 266-287.

106 To be sure, ol nepl yuaewq are first attested in Plato's Lysis (214b5).

107 Barker 2007, 306.

Diller H. Der griechische Naturbegriff. Neue Jahrbücher für antike und deutsche Bildung. 1939, 114, 241257 = Diller H. Kleine Schriften zur antiken Literatur. Munich, Beck, 1971, 144-161.

Frisk H. Griechisches etymologisches Wörterbuch. Vol. 2. Heidelberg, Carl Winter, 1970.

Gemelli Marciano L. Lire du début, Philosophie antique. 2007, 17, 7-37.

Graham D. W. The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy. Part 1. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2010.

Hardy E. Der Begriff der Physis in der griechischen Philosophie. Berlin, Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1884.

Heidel W. A. Notes on Philolaus. American Journal of Philology. 1907, 28, 77-81.

Heidel W. A. nspi puas«;. A Study of the Conception of Nature Among the Pre-Socratics. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 1910, 45, 79-133.

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

Heinemann G. Die Entwicklung des Begriffs physis bis Aristoteles, in: Astrid Schürmann (ed.). Physik / Mechanik (Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften in der Antike, 3). Stuttgart, Steiner, 2005, 16-60.

Heinemann G. Vorlesungen über die Geschichte des griechischen Naturbegriffs bis Aristoteles. Uni Kassel, 2011-2012, work in progress. Available at: https://www.academia.edu/14935955/Vorlesungen (05.05.2018).

Heinimann F. Nomos und Physis. Basel, F. Reinhardt, 1945.

Holwerda D. Commentatio de vocis quae est puai; vi atque usu praesertim in graecitate Aristotele anteriore (Diss). Groningen, 1955.

Huffman C. A. Philolaus of Croton. Pythagorean and Presocratic. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Huffman C. A. Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher and Mathematician King. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Joly R. La question hippocratique et le témoignage du Phèdre. Revue des Études Grecques. 1961, 74, 69-92.

Kahn Ch. H. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology. New York, Columbia University Press, 1960.

Kirk G. S. Heraclitus, The Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1954.

Kirk G. S., Raven J. E., Schofield M. The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.

Kroll W. Lobon von Argos, RE 1922, 11, 931-933.

Kühn J.-H., Fleischer U. (eds.). Index Hippocraticus. Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1989.

Laks A., Most G. (eds). Early Greek Philosophy. Western Greek Thinkers. Part 1. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 2016.

Leisegang H. Physis. RE 1941, 20.1, 1130-1164.

Lloyd G. E. R. The Hippocratic Question. Classical Quarterly 1975, 25, 171-192.

Lovejoy A. O. The Meaning of puai; in the Greek Physiologers. Philosophical Review 1909, 18, 369-83.

Lovejoy A. O. [Rev.] Heidel W. A. nspi puasw;. A Study of the Conception of Nature Among the Pre-Socrat-ics. Philosophical Review 1910, 19, 665-667.

Luria S. Democritea. Leningrad, Nauka, 1970.

Mansfeld J. [Rev.] Naddaf G. L'origine et l'évolution du concept grec de Phusis [...] Mnemosyne 1997, 50, 754-758.

Mannsperger D. Physis bei Platon. Berlin, de Gruyter, 1969.

Mejer J. Demetrius of Magnesia: On Poets and Authors of the Same Name. Hermes 1981, 109, 447-472.

Müller C. W. [Rev.] Schmalzriedt E. Peri Physeos. Zur Frühgeschichte der Buchtitel [...] Gnomon. 1978, 50, 628-638.

Naddaf G. The Greek Concept of Nature. Albany, NY, SUNY Press, 2005.

Nussbaum M. Eleatic Conventionalism and Philolaus on the Conditions of Thought. Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 1979, 83, 63-108.

Patzer H. Physis: Grundlegung zu einer Geschichte des Wortes. Wiesbaden, Steiner, 1993.

Pohlenz M. Nomos und Physis. Hermes 1953, 81, 418-438.

Primavesi O. Empedokles, in: H. Flashar, D. Bremer, G. Rechenauer (eds). Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie. Vol. 1: Die Philosophie der Antike. Frühgriechische Philosophie, Basel: Schwabe, 2013, 667-739.

Rechenauer G. Thukydides und die hippokratische Medizin: Naturwissenschaftliche Methodik als Modell für Geschichtsdeutung. Hildesheim, Georg Olms, 1991.

Robinson T. M. Contrasting Arguments: An Edition of the Dissoi Logoi. Salem, NH, Ayer, 1979.

Rosetti L. Caratteristiche tipologiche dei trattati Пер! фйаешс; nei secoli VI-V a. C. Noua tellus 2006, 24, 111-146.

Schirren T. Xenophanes, in: H. Flashar, D. Bremer, G. Rechenauer (eds). Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie. Vol. 1: Die Philosophie der Antike. Frühgriechische Philosophie. Basel6 Schwabe, 2013, 339-374.

Schmalzriedt E. Peri Physeos. Zur Frühgeschichte der Buchtitel. Munich, W. Fink, 1970.

Schofield M. [Rev.] Naddaf G. The Greek Concept ofNature [...] Classical Review 2006, 56, 14-16.

Sedley D. Parmenides and Melissus, in: A. A. Long (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999, 113-133.

Timpanaro Cardini M. Pitagorici antichi: Testimonianze e frammenti. Florence, La Nuova Italia, 1961 = Milan, Bompiani, 2010.

Woodbridge F. J. E. The Dominant Conception of the Earliest Greek Philosophy. Philosophical Review 1901, 10, 359-374.

Zhmud L. The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity. Berlin, de Gruyter, 2006.

Zhmud L. Pythagoras and the Early Pythagoreans. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012.

Received: 12.02.2018 Final version received: 17.04.2018

Physis в пифагорейской традиции

Леонид Яковлевич Жмудь

Санкт-Петербургский филиал Института истории естествознания и техники им. С. И. Вавилова

РАН, Российская Федерация, 199034, Санкт-Петербург, Университетская наб., д. 5; l.zhmud@spbu.ru

В статье обсуждается понятие physis, встречающееся во фрагментах пифагорейцев Филолая из Кротона и Архита из Тарента. Отталкиваясь от дискуссии о двух основных значениях physis, «росте» и «бытии», которая велась среди англоязычных (начало XX в.), а затем среди немецких (середина XX в.) исследователей античной философии (раздел 2), статья аргументирует, что Филолай был, вероятно, автором первого трактата Пер! фиаеш;, как об этом свидетельствует писатель I в. до н. э. Диоген из Магнезии. Остальные свидетельства о книгах досократиков, озаглавленных Пер! фиаеш;, являются поздними и ненадежными (раздел 3). Вопреки мнению издателя Филолая К. Хафме-на, а фит; во фрагментах B 1 и 6, употребляемая неатрибутивно и с артиклем, обозначает все, что возникло из двух основных начал, apeira и perainonta, под воздействием harmonia, и существует в этом мироустройстве (B 2, 6). Physis не вечна и познаваема лишь частично (раздел 4). В отличие от Филолая, у Архита не было учения о началах, и его эпистемология не была ограничена метафизическими принципами. Архит рассматривает physis в космологическом и эпистемологическом плане как «природу целого», доступную человеческому познанию (B 1). Не ставя процессу познания каких-либо ограничений, как это делал Филолай, Архит подкрепляет заявление последнего о том, что «все вещи, которые нам известны, имеют число» (B 4), тем, что делает четыре mathemata основным познавательным инструментом в научных исследованиях природы (раздел 5).

Ключевые слова: Филолай из Кротона, Архит из Тарента, пифагорейская традиция, physis.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.