Научная статья на тему 'Decidability of multi-modal logic ltk of linear time and knowledge'

Decidability of multi-modal logic ltk of linear time and knowledge Текст научной статьи по специальности «Математика»

CC BY
57
8
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
Ключевые слова
EffECTIVE fiNITE MODEL PROPERTY / МНОГОМОДАЛЬНАЯ ЛОГИКА / ЛИНЕЙНАЯ ВРЕМЕННАЯ ЛОГИКА / РАЗРЕШИМОСТЬ / ЭФФЕКТИВНАЯ ФИНИТНАЯ АППРОКСИМИРУЕМОСТЬ / MULTI-MODAL LOGIC / TEMPORAL LOGIC / EPISTEMIC LOGIC / DECIDABILITY

Аннотация научной статьи по математике, автор научной работы — Lukyanchuk Alexandra N.

Thepaperinvestigates modal(temporal-model) logicsbased at a semantic approach with models combining knowledge and time. We introduce multi-modal logics LT Kr and LT Kir containing modalities for knowledge and time as the sets of all LT Kr -valid, and LT Kir -valid formulae for a class of special LT Kr frames, LT Kir -frames, respectively. The main results of this paper are theorems stating that LT Kr and LT Kir are decidable; we also give an explicit solving algorithm.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.

Текст научной работы на тему «Decidability of multi-modal logic ltk of linear time and knowledge»

УДК 510.665

Decidability of Multi-modal Logic LTK of Linear Time and Knowledge

Alexandra N. Lukyanchuk*

Institute of Mathematics and Computer Science, Siberian Federal University, Svobodny, 79, Krasnoyarsk, 660041

Russia

Received 25.12.2012, received in revised form 25.01.2013, accepted 25.02.2013 The paper investigates modal (temporal-model) logics based at a semantic approach with models combining knowledge and time. We introduce multi-modal logics LTKr and LTKir containing modalities for knowledge and time as the sets of all LTKr-valid, and LTKir-valid formulae for a class of special LTKr-frames, LTKir -frames, respectively. The main results of this paper are theorems stating that LTKr and LTKir are decidable; we also give an explicit solving algorithm.

Keywords: multi-modal logic, temporal logic, epistemic logic, decidability, effective finite model property

Introduction

Nowadays modal and multi-modal propositional logics describing human reasoning and agents' behavior is an active area [1-3]. It is well known that the combination of temporal and knowledge modalities provides an highly expressive and efficient language (cf. [1, 4]). Multimodal logics generated by adjoining operators representing time and knowledge to the classical propositional calculus PC are very effective for modeling reasoning, where agents, who possess a certain knowledge, are operating in the processes of computation in a flow of time (see [1,3,4]).

In this paper we study a semantic approach for construction models combining knowledge and time. Some linear logics using the knowledge and time are investigated in a papers of V.Rybakov and E.Calardo [5-7]. Complete axiomatization of a number of different logics involving conditions for knowledge and time can be founded in [3]. The aim of this article is to prove decidability of multi-modal logics LTKr, LTKir with intransitive, reflexive/irreflexive relation of time.

We consider time as a linear and discrete sequence of states. Each state consists of a set of information points connected by modal relations Ri. To bring it more exact, Ri says which information points are effectively available for the agent i: it specifies the piece of information that the agent may access at given moment. Agents operating synchronously and each agent knows what time it is and distinguishes present from future time. So logic is semantically defined as the set of all LTKr-valid (LTKir-valid) formulae, where LTKr-frames (LTKir-frames) are multi-modal Kripke-frames combining a linear and discrete representation of the flow of time with special S5-like modalities, defined at each time cluster and representing knowledge. The main result of our paper are theorems stating that LTKr and LTKir have the effective finite model property and hence, that they are decidable.

* [email protected] © Siberian Federal University. All rights reserved

1. Preliminaries

First we recall basic definitions, notation and known results used in this article (for more detailed information about the subject see [8, 9]).

The language Lltk consists of a countable set of propositional letters P := (pi,... ,pn,... }, the standard boolean operations and the set of modal operations (DT, CU, □ (i G I)}. Well formed formulae (wff's) are defined in the standard way, in particular, if A is a wff, than □TA, D^A, □iA(i G /) are wff's. We denote by Fma(LLTK) the set of all the wff's of LLTK (in the sequel, in an expression formula we always refer to a formula from Fma(LLTK)). The intended meaning of the modal operations is: (a) DTA for logic LTKr means that the formula A true in the current state and will be true in the next state. DTA in logic LTKjr means that the formula A will be true in the next state. (b) D^A means that A is known everywhere in the present time-cluster (i.e. A is part of the environmental knowledge); (c) □jA(i G I) stands for the agent i (operating in the system) knows A in the current state. Semantics for the language LLTK is based on a linear and discrete flow of time, associating a time point with any natural number n.

Definition 1.1. A k-modal Kripke-frame is a tuple F = (Wf, R1,..., Rk} where Wf is a nonempty set of worlds and each Rj is some binary relation on Wf .

Definition 1.2. Given a Kripke-frame F = (Wf, R1,..., Rk}, for any Rj(1 ^ i ^ k) an Rj-cluster of worlds is a subset CRi of Wf s.t.: VwVz G CRi (wRjz & zRjw) and Vz G WfVw G CRi(((wRjz & zRjw) ^ z G CRi). For any Rj, CRi(w) is the Rj-cluster s.t. w G CRi. Given two Rj-clusters Cm and Cj the expression CmRjCj is an abbreviation for Vw G Cm, Vz G Cj(wRjz).

Definition 1.3. An LTKr-frame is a multi-modal frame F = (Wf, RT, R^, R1,..., Rk}, where:

(a) Wf is the disjoint union of certain nonempty sets Cn: Wf := U Cn where J = [0, L]

nEJ

and L G N or J = N.

(b) RT is the linear, reflexive and intransitive relation on Wf such that: VwV z G WF(wRTz ^ [3n G J((w G Cn)&(z G Cn))] V [3 n + 1 G J((w G Cn)&(z G Cn+1))]).

(c) R^ is a universal relation on any Cn G Wf : V wV z G Wf (wR^z ^ 3 n G J((w G C„)&(z G Cn))).

(d) V i G I, Rj is some equivalence relation on Cn. Let ltkr be the class of all LTKr-frames.

Definition 1.4. An LTKjr-frame is a multi-modal frame F = (Wf, Rt, R~, R1,..., Rk}, where:

(a) Wf is the disjoint union of certain nonempty sets Cn: Wf := U Cn where J = [0, L]

nEJ

and L G N or J = N.

(b) RT is the linear, irreflexive and intransitive relation on Wf such that: VwVz G WF (wRT z ^3 n + 1 G J ((w G Cn)&(z G Cn+1))).

(c) R^ is a universal relation on any Cn G Wf : V wV z G Wf (wR^z ^ 3 n G J ((w G

Cn)&(z G Cn))).

(d) V i G I, Rj is some equivalence relation on Cn. Let ltkir be the class of all LTKjr-frames.

Such frames simulate the situation in which agents, having a certain knowledge background at any moment, are operating in the linear flow of time. Each time-cluster (i.e. an RT-cluster) Cn consists of a set of information points that are available at the moment n. The relation RT

is the connection of such information points by the flow of time. That is, given two information points w and z, the expression wRTz means either that w and z are both available at a moment n, or that z will be available in the moment n +1 with respect to w. Since the relation R^ connects all the information-points available at the same moment, it is intended to represent a sort of environmental knowledge, that is, the whole information potentially available for the agent at a given time. The relation Ri says which information points are effectively available for the agent i at any given moment.

Definition 1.5. Given a Kripke-frame F, a model Mf on F is a tuple Mf = (F, V) where V is a valuation of a set P of propositional letters in F. That is Vp G P, V(p) Ç Wf .

Given a model M = (F, V), where F is an LTKr-frame (LTKir-frame), the valuation V can be extended in the standard way from the set P onto all well formed formulae constructed from P. In particular, Vw G Wf:

(a) (F, w) =v p & w G V(p);

(b) (F,w) =v OtA & Vz G Wf(wRtz ^ (F,z) =v A);

(c) (F, w) =v A & Vz G Wf(wR^z ^ (F, z) =v A);

(d) Vi G I, (F, w) =v OiA &Vz G Wf(wRiz ^ (F,z) =v A).

A formula A is said to be true in the model M at the world w if (F, w) =v A. A formula A is true in the model M, notation F =v A, if V w G Wf, (F, w) =v A. A is valid in the frame F, notation F = A if, for any valuation V for F, F =v A. The expression V(A) is an abbreviation for the set {w | w =v A}.

Definition 1.6. Logic LTKr is the set of all LTKr-valid formulae:

LTKr := {A e Fma(LLTKr)|VF e ltkr(F = A)}. If A belongs to LTKr, then A is said to be a theorem of LTKr.

Definition 1.7. Logic LTKir is the set of all LTKir-valid formulae:

LTKir := {A e Fma(CLTKir)| VF e ltkir(F = A)}.

If A belongs to LTKir, then A is said to be a theorem of LTKir.

Definition 1.8. Logic L has effective finite model property (efmp) if there is a computable function f such that for every formula A £ L, there is a finite model (F,V}: F =V A and F =v B, for any formula B e L, where | | Wf| | < f | | A11 .

Definition 1.9. Logic L is decidable if there is an algorithm which, for any formula A, determines whether A e L holds.

Definition 1.10. Let A e Fma(LLTK). Modal time degree td(A) of A is defined as follows: td(p) = td(T) = td(±) = 0; td(-a) = td(a); td(a ^ ¡3) = td(a V ¡3) = td(a A ¡3) = max(td(a), td(f3)); td(0^a) = td(Oia) = td(a); td(OTa) = td(a) + 1.

Definition 1.11. Let A e Fma(LLTK). Modal time-static degree m(A) of A is defined as: m(p) = m(T) = m(^) = 0; m(—a) = m(a); m(a ^ 3) = m(a V 3) = m(a A 3) = max(m(a),m(3)); m(OTa) = m(a); m(O^a) = m(Oia) = m(a) + 1.

2. Effective finite model property

The main question we will give an answer is: whether LTKr and LTKir have the effective finite model property (efmp). We will first prove below that LTKr has the efmp and hence it is decidable.

Theorem 2.1. The logic LTKr has the effective finite model property.

Proof. Take a formula A such that A G LTKr and let td(A) = n. Then there are an LTKr-frame F = ((U;eJ C}, RT, R-, Ri,..., Rk) (J = [0, L], L G N or J = N), valuation V and a world x G Cr such that (F, x) =V A. Denote the basic set (U;eJ C;} as Wf.

We start by reducing the number of worlds belonging to each RT-cluster C of worlds from Wf using the standard filtration technique. We briefly sketch it below. Let Sw6(A) be the set of all the sub-formulae of A. Define the equivalence relation « on F as follows:

VwVz G WF(w « z ^ wR^z & zR^w & VB G Sw6(A) ((F, w) B ^ (F, z)) =V B). Then we define the quotient set of the original model: Vw G Wf ([w] := (z | w « z}, [C] := U[w]ec[w]). The filtrated model M1 is define as M1 := (F1; V1) where:

(a) Wf := (U;ej[C;]};

(b) [w]Ri[z] ^ wR^z;

(c) [w]RT[z] ^ wRTz;

(d) [w]R1[z](1 < i < k) ^ ([w] G C & [z] G C & VB G Sw6(A) ((F,w) =v DjB ^ (F, z) =v DiB);

(e) Vp G Sub(A)(V1(p) := {[w]| w G V(p)}).

Since the model described is the result of a filtration, the standard filtration lemma holds:

Lemma 2.1. For any formula B G Sw6(A) and for any world w G Wf, (F, w) =V B ^ (F1, [w]) =Vl B.

Corollary 2.1. (F1, [x]) =Vl A.

We define now the model M as follows:

M = (([Cr], [Cr+1 ], [Cr+2],..., [Cj]}, RT, Ri, R1,..., Rk, V1)

, . f r + n, if F1 is infinite or r + n ^ L; where j = < T

[ L, if r + n > L.

It is easy to see, that M consists of at most n +1 clusters.

Now we are going to show that if the model (F1, V1) refutes a formula A, then the model M also refutes A.

Lemma 2.2. For any formula a s.t. td(a) = 0 and for any world [y] G ([Cr] U [Cr+1] U [Cr+2] U

... u [Cj]}

(F1, [y])=vi a ^(M, [y]) = a, (2.1)

i.e. truth of time-static formulae on model M remains the same.

Proof. The proof can be given by induction on modal time-static degree m(a) of formula a. If m(a) = 0, then a consists of only propositional variables and the standard boolean operations. In this case the truth of a is determined by the valuation of propositional variables at the world [y] G {[Cr] U [Cr+1] U [Cr+2] U ... U [Cj]}. Thus, by construction of a model M, we have (F1, [y]) =Vi a ^ (M, [y]) = a.

Let m(a) = l + 1 and for all other a s.t. m(a) ^ l condition (2.1) holds. By definition wff, formula a can be obtained from the sub-formulae by is several ways specified below. We will show that condition (2.1) is true in all the cases.

1) Let a = Di«1 where m(a1) = I. If (F1, [y]) =v1 a and [y] G {[Cr] U [Cr+1] U [Cr+2] U ... U [Cj]}, then V[z] G [C(y)], (F1, [z]) a1. By the inductive hypothesis it follows V[z] G [C(y)], (M, [z]) = a1. Hence (M, [y]) = a. The proof of converse case is similar.

2) Now let Vi e {1,...,k},a = H^ai and m(ax) = l. If (Fi, [y]} ==vi a with [y] e {[Cr] U [Cr+i] U [Cr+2] U ... U [Cj]}, then for all worlds z s.t. [y]R1[z] we have (F1, [z]} =Vl a1. By the inductive hypothesis it follows V[z] : [y]R1[z], (M, [z]} = a1. i.e. (M, [y]} = a. The proof of converse case is similar.

3) Suppose that a = a1 oa2 with o e {A, V}, besides max(m(a1), m(a2)) = l + 1, a1 = □ai and a2 = □a2 (£ e 1,..., k}). Then for any world [y] e {[Cr] U [Cr+1] U [Cr+2] U ... U [Cj]} holds (F1, [y]} =Vi a1 o a2 ^^ (F1, [y]} =Vi a1 and/or (F1, [y]} =Vi a2 ^^ (M, [y]} = a1 and/or (M, [y]} = a2 ^^ (M, [y]} = a1 o a2.

Also if a = —a1, m(a1) = l + 1 and a1 = □a2, then V[y] e {[Cr] U [Cr+1] U [Cr+2] U ... U [Cj]} by previous proof we have (F1, \y]) =Vl —a1 ^^ (F1, [y]} ==Vl a1 ^^ (M, [y]} = a1 ^^ (M, [y]} = -a1.

Hence applying boolean operations does not change the truth of relation (2.1). Thus, composition of formulae of the forms 1), 2), and 3), by using a finite number of boolean operations holds (2.1).

Thus, by induction at the last step we have the following statement: Va s.t. td(a) = 0 and V[y] e {[Cr] U [Cr+1] U [Cr+2] U ... U [Cj]} holds (F1, [y]} =Vi a ^ (M, [y]} = a.

So if formula a contains only time-static modalities, then the truth of a is determined only by the valuation of propositional variables at the worlds of cluster [C(y)], so the condition (2.1) is true and Lemma 2.2 is proved. □

Lemma 2.3. For any formula B e Sub(A) and for any world [x] e [Cr],

(F1, [x]} =Vi B ^ (M, [x]} = B

Proof. If the length of generated subframe Cf of frame F1 less then n, then model M coincides with the submodel (Cf, V1}, which already refuted the formula B and is already finite (has length < n). It remains to consider the case when the length of the subframe Cf is longer then n + 1, or frame F1 is infinite. In this case the length of model M is n +1 (i.e. j — r = n).

By definition of wff, formula B is constructed from sub-formulas a and 3 one of the following ways:

a) B = dTa, td(a) = l, (0 < l < n — 1);

b) B = d^a,td(a) = l, (0 < l < n);

c) B = □ia,td(a) = l, (1 < i < k) and (0 < l < n);

d) B = a o 3, o e {A, V}, max(td(a),td(3)) = l and (0 < l < n);

e) B = —a, td(a) = l, (0 < l < n).

Our next step is to show that for any formula B such that td(B) < s (s e [0, n]) and for all m such that r < j — m — s, (F1, [x]} =Vi B ^^ (M, [x]} = B where [x] e [Cj-m-s]. We conduct an induction on the modal time degree td(B) of formula B.

The inductive base: if td(B) = 0 using Lemma 2.2 we have (F1, [x]} =Vi B ^^ (M, [x]} = B.

The inductive hypothesis: suppose that for formula B s.t. td(B) < s with s e [0,n — 1], for all m s.t. r < j — m — s and for worlds [x] e [Cj-m-s] assertion (F1, [x]} =Vi B ^^ (M, [x]} = B is true.

The inductive step: let B = dTa (td(a) = s). If (F1, [x]} =Vi B where [x] e [Cj-m-(s+1)], then (F1, [x]} =Vi a and for all worlds [y] s.t [x]RT[y] the following is carried out: (F1, [y]} =Vi a. By the inductive hypothesis it implies (M, [x]} = a & V[y] : [x]RT[y], (M, [y]} = a. That is (M, [x]} = B and hence (F1, [x]} =Vi B (M, [x]} = B. The proof of converse case is similar.

Now show that the application of boolean operations and □ to a formula a of the form a) holds the case true. Note that in cases b)-e) the modal time degree of sub-formulas a and p does not increase and does not require checking the truth of B in the neighboring clusters.

Let B = □ia with td(a) = s + 1 and a = DTa'. If (F1, [x]) =Vl B with [x] G [Cj_m_(s+1)], then V[z] G [C(x)], (F1, [z]) =Vl a. By previous proof we have V[z] G [C(x)], (M, [z]) = a, hence (M , [x] ) = B. The proof of converse case is similar.

Let B = □.¿a with i G (1,..., k}, td(a) = s + 1 and a = DTa'. If (F1, [x]) =Vl B where [x] G [Cj_m_(s+1)], then for all worlds z s.t. [x]R1[z] the following (F1, [z]) =Vl a holds. By previous proof we have V[z] : [x]R1[z], (M, [z]) = a or, in other words, (M, [x]) = B. The proof of converse case is similar.

Let B = a o p with o G (A, V}, max(td(a), td(p)) = s +1, a = DTa' and p = DTp'. Then for any world [x] G [Cj_m_(s+1)] we have (F1, [x]) =Vl a o p ^^ (F1, [x]) =Vl a and/or (F1, [x]) p ^ (m, [x]) = a and/or (M, [x]) = p ^ (M, [x]) = a o p.

Now let B = -a,td(a) = s + 1 and a = DTa'. Then V[x] G [Cj_m_(s+1)], (F1, [x]) =Vl -a ^ (F1, [x]) a ^ (M, [x]) = a ^ (M, [x]) = -a.

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

So applying time-static operations does not change the truth of relation (F1, [x]) |=Vl B ^^ (M, [x]) = B. Thus, composition of sub-formulas a and p of the form a) with time degree s (0 < s < n), by using a finite number of boolean operations, □i or □j, holds this relation true.

Thus, by induction at step n+1 we have the following statement: VB G Sw6(A) s.t. tb(B) < n and V[x] G [Cr] holds (F1, [x]) =v1 B ^^ (M, [x]) = B. Thus Lemma 2.3 is proved. □

Corollary 2.2. (M, [x]) = A.

Note that the model M is a linear chain of at most n +1 clusters, and each RT-cluster contains a finite number of worlds, bounded by the size of A, namely 11 C | | < 2|S"6(A)| for each RT-cluster C. So we can conclude that | | M | | < (n + 1)2|Sub(A)|. Thus, if the formula A does not belong to LTKr, then there is a finite model M (of effectively computable size) which refutes A. Hence, the logic LTKr has effective finite model property. Therefore we immediately derive:

Theorem 2.2. The logic LTKr is decidable.

Proof. The deciding algorithm for arbitrary formula a looks as follows:

1. Define the modal-time degree for a: td(a) = n.

2. Construct all possible linear LTKr-frames, which contain at most n +1 time-clusters and bounded by the size of a.

3. Consider all valuations of variables of a such that the resulting models are non-isomorphic. Since the number of variables of formula a is finite, the number of non-isomorphic models is also finite. If a is true in all such models, then it is the theorem of LTKr, if at least one model refutes a, then it is not the theorem of LTKr. □

Now consider the logic LTKir.

Theorem 2.3. The logic LTKir has the effective finite model property and hence it is decidable.

Proof. The proving schemata almost verbatim follows the proof of the case for LTKr, but the model M in this case is defined as follows:

M = (([Cr], [Cr+1], [Cr+2],..., [Cj]}, RT, Ri, R1,..., Rk, V)

, . f r + n + 1, if F is infinite or r + n + 1 < L; 1 where j = < T „ > and for time-cluster Cr+n+1 the

\ L, if r + n + 1 > L, J r+n+1

relation RT is defined to be reflexive. The other steps of the proof for this case may be easy

adjusted from the previous proof.

Since there is a effectively finite model which refutes any formula A which does not belong to LTKir, then LTKir has the effective finite model property, and hence LTKir is decidable. □

References

[1] R.Fagin, J.Y.Halpern, Y.Moses, M.Y.Vardi, Reasoning About Knowledge, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachussets, 1995.

[2] R.Bull, K.Segerberg, Basic Modal Logic. In D.Gabbay and F.Guenthner (Eds), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, II, 135-165, Reidel, Dordrechtn The Netherlands, 1984.

[3] J.Y.Halpern, R.Van Der Meyden, M.Y.Vardi, Complete Axiomatization for Reasoning About Knowledge and Time, SIAM Journal on Computing, 33(2004), no. 3, 674-703.

[4] R.H.Thomason, Combination of tense and modality. In D.Gabbay and F.Guenthner (Eds), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, II, 135-165, Reidel Dordrechtn, The Netherlands, 1984.

[5] E.Calardo V.V.Rybakov. Combining time and knowledge, semantic approach, Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 34(2005), no. 1, 13-21.

[6] E.Calardo. Admissible inference rules in the linear logic of knowledge and time LTK, Logic Journal of the IGPL, 14(2006), no. 1, 15-34.

[7] E.Calardo, V.V. Rybakov. An axiomatisation for the multi-modal logic of knowledge and linear time LTK, Logic Journal of the IGPL, 0(2013) , 1-16.

[8] V.V.Rybakov, Admissibility of Logical Inference Rules Elsevier Science, Amsterdam, 1997.

[9] A.Chagrov, M.Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic. Oxford, Clarendon press, 1997.

Разрешимость многомодальной линейной логики знания и времени LTK

Александра Н. Лукьянчук

В представленной статье используется семантический подход к построению моделей, комбинирующих модальности знания и времени. Семантически вводятся многомодальные логики LTKr и LTKir, содержащие модальности знания и времени как множество формул, истинных на фреймах специального вида. Главным результатом работы являются теоремы об эффективной финитной аппроксимируемости и, как следствие, 'разрешимости данных логик.

Ключевые слова: многомодальная логика, линейная временная логика, разрешимость, эффективная финитная аппроксимируемость.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.