XAK: 519.810 MSC2010: 91.830
A NEW APPROACH TO GUARANTEED SOLUTIONS OF MULTICRITERIA CHOICE PROBLEMS: PARETO CONSIDERATION OF SAVAGE-NIEHANS RISK AND OUTCOMES
© V. I. Zhukovskiy
Lomonosov Moscow State University Faculty of Computational Mathematics and Cybernetics Department of Optimal Control Leninskiye Gory, GSP-1, Moscow, 119991, Russia e-mail: [email protected]
© L. V. Zhukovskaya
Federal State Budgetary Institution of Science Central Economic and Mathematical Institute of the
Russian Academy of Sciences (CEMI RAS) Nakhimovskii prosp., 47, Moscow, 117418, Russia e-mail: [email protected]
© Y. S. Mukhina
Lomonosov Moscow State University Faculty of Mechanics and Mathematics Department of Higher Algebra Leninskiye Gory, GSP-1, Moscow, 119991, Russia e-mail: [email protected]
a new approach to guaranteed solutions of multioriteria choice problems: pareto consideration of savage-niehans risk and outcomes.
Zhukovskiy V. I., Zhukovskaya L. V., Mukhina Y. S.
Abstract. This article considers three new approaches to important problems of mathematical game theory and multicriteria choice.The first approach ensures payoff increase with simultaneous risk reduction in the Savage Niehans sense in multicriteria choice problem and noncooperative games. The second approach allow us to stabilize coalitional structures in cooperative games without side payments under uncertainty. The third approach serves to integrate the selfish Nash equilibrium with the altruistic Berge equilibrium. Note that the investigations involve a special Germeier convolution of criteria and calculation of its saddle point in mixed strategies.
Keywords: Savage Niehans risk, minimax regret, uncertainties, multicriteria choice, Pareto consideration
1. Prologue
This article introduces an original approach to multicriteria choice problems under uncertainty: a decision maker (DM) seeks not only to increase the guaranteed values of each criterion, but also to reduce the guaranteed risk of such increase. The approach lies at the junction of multicriteria choice problems [1, 2] and the Savage-Niehans principle of minimax regret (risk) [3-5]. More specifially, we will employ the notion of a weakly efficient estimate and the Germeier theorem [6, 7] from the theory of multicriteria choice problems and an estimated value of the regret function as the Savage-Niehans risk from the principle of minimax regret [3]. Considerations are restricted to interval-type uncertainty, i.e., the DM merely knows the limits of a range of values, without any probabilistic characteristics.We suggest a new concept — the Slater-maximal strongly-guaranteed solution in outcomes and risks (SGOR) — and establish its existence under standard assumptions of mathematical programming (continuous criteria, compact strategy sets and compact uncertainty [9] - [12]). As a possible application, the SGOR in the diversification problem of a deposit into sub-deposits in different currencies is calculated in explicit form.
2. Introduction
Consider a multicriteria choice problem under uncertainty (MCPU)
rc = <N,X,Y,f (x,y)>,
where N = {1,..., N}(N < 2) denotes the set of numbers assigned to the elements fi(x, y) of a vector criterion f (x,y) = (fx(x,y), ...,fN(x,y)); X C Rn is the set of alternatives x; Y C Rm forms the set of interval uncertainty y. For Savage-Niehans risk function design, we will also use the strategic uncertainties y(x) : X ^ Y, denoting their set by YX.
At the conceptual level, it is often assumed that the DM in the problem Tc seeks for an alternative x G X that maximizes the values of all criteria (outcomes) under any realization of the uncertainty y G Y .In this article we will also take into account N new criteria - the risk posed by increasing these outcomes. Thus, the problem setup with include N additional criteria, i.e., the Savage-Niehans risk function associated with outcome increase.
Thus, this article will justify in mathematical terms the next design method of alternatives in the MCPUs that simultaneously "hits into targets" namely, achieving higher of all outcomes under smaller risks posed by them.
The Savage-Niehans Principle of Minimax Regret
In 1939 A. Wald, a Romanian mathematician who emigrated to the USA in 1938, introduced the maxmin principle, also known as the principle of guaranteed outcome. This principle allows one to find a guaranteed outcome [13, 14] in a single-criterion choice problem under uncertainty (SCPU). Almost a decade later, German mathematician J. Niehans (1948) and American mathematician, economist and statistician L. Savage (1951) suggested the principle of minimax regret (PMR) for building guaranteed risks in the SCPUs [4], In the modern literature, this principle is also refered to as the Savage risk or the Niehans-Savage criterion. Interestingly, during World War II Savage worked as an assistant of J. von Neumann, which surely contributed to the appearance of the PMR.Note that the autos of two most remarkable dissertations in economics and statistics are annually awarded the Savage Prize, which was established in 1971 in the USA.
For the single-criterion problem r = (X, Y, 0(x, y)), the PMR is to construct a pair (xr, R) 6 X x R that satisfies the chain of equalities [12]
R1 = maxR^x7' , y) = minmaxR^x, y), (1)
y& xgX y&
where te savage-Niehans risk function has the form
R^(x, y) = max0(z,y) - 0(x,y). (2)
The value R^ given by (1) is called the Savage-Niehans risk in the problem rx. The risk function R^(x,y) assessed the difference between the realized value of the criterion 0(x, y) and its best-case value max 0(z, y) from the DM's view. Obviously, the DM
zgX
strives to reduce R^ (x, y) as much as possible with an appropriately chosen alternative x 6 X, naturally expecting the strongest opposition from the uncertainty in accordance with the principle of guaranteed result (formula (1)). Therefore, adhering to (1)-(2), the DM is an optimist seeking for the best-case value max 0(x,y). In contrast, the pessimistic DM is oriented towards the worth-case result — the Wald maximin solutions (x0, 0° = max min0(x, y) = min0(x0, y)).
In the sequel, we will consider that the DM in the problem Tc is an optimist: for each element /j(x,y)(i 6 N) of the vector criterion f (x,y), he forms a corresponding Savage-Niehans risk function:
Ri(x,y) = max fi(z,y) - fi(x,y) (i G N). (3)
Note two important aspects as follows. First, each criterion fi(x,y) from Tc has its own risk Ri(x,y) (see (3)). Second, the DM tries to choose alternatives x G X so as to reduce all risks Ri(x,y), expecting any realization of the strategic uncertainty y(■) G YX, y(x) : X ^ Y.
Remark 1. The models rc arise naturally, e.g., in economics: a seller in a market is interested in maximizing his profits under import uncertainty.
The uncertainties present in the problem r lead to the sets
0(x,Y) = {0(x,y) | Vy G Y}, which are induced by an alternative x G X. The set 0(x, Y) can be reduced using risks. What is a proper comprehension of risk? A well-known Russian expert in optimization, T. Sirazetdinov [16], claims that today there is no rigorous mathematical definition of risk. The monograph [17, p. 15] even suggested sixteen possible concepts of risk. Most of them require statistical data of uncertainty. However, in many cases the DM does not posses such information for objective reasons.
Thus, here risks will be understood as possible deviations of relized values from the disired ones. Note that this definition (in particular, the Savage-Niehans risk) is in good agreement with the conventional notion of microeconomic risk; e.g., see [19, pp. 40-50].
Risk management is a topical problem of economics: in 1990, H. Markowitz was awarded the Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences "for having developed the theory of portfolio choice". In this article, the idea of his approach will be extended to the multicriteria choice problems and conflicts under uncertainty. In publications on microeconomics (e.g., see [18, p.5], [19, p.103]) all decision makers are divided into three categories: risk-averse, risk-neutral and risk-seeking. Further the DM is assumed to be a risk-neutral and, of course, an optimist.
Strong Guarantees and Transition from rc to 2N-Criteria Choice
Problem
For each of the N criteria fi(x, y) (i G N), construct the corresponding risk function Ri(x,y) using formulas (3), thereby extending the MCPU Tc to the 2N-criteria choice problem
<N,X,Y, {fi(x,y), -Ri(x,y)}i£N>. (4)
In (4) the sets N, X and Y are the same as in rc, while the vector criterion f (x, y) has an additional term in the form of the N-dimensional vector —R(x,y) = (—Ri(x, y),..., —RN(x,y)). Here the minus sign reflects a uniform effect of any alternative x G X on each criterion fi(x, y)(i G N). More specifically, in problem (4) the DM chooses an alternative x G X in order to increase as much as possible the value of each element fi(x, y) and —Ri(x, y)(i G N) of the two N-dimensional vectors f (x, y) and —R(x, y). Moreover, the DM must expect any realization of uncertainty y G Y (note that an increase of —Ri(x, y) is equivalent to a decrease of Ri(x, y) due to the minus sign and Ri(x, y) > 0).
Now, consider the strong guarantees of criteria. In a series of papers [21, 22] the authors suggested three methods to take the uncertain factors into account — an analog of saddle point [22] and two analogs of maximin [21], namely, strong and vector guarantees. Note that strong guarantee is used below, while vector guarantee was applied.
Definition 1. A scalar function fi[x] is called a strong guarantee of a criterion fi(x, y) : X ^ Y if, for each x G X,
fi[x] < fi(x,y) Vy G Y (i G N).
Remark 2. Obviously, the function fi[x] = min fi(x,y) Vx G X is a strong guarantee
yeY
of fi(x, y). Hence, we have an explicit design method for the strong guarantees of all 2N criteria from (4).
Let us find the strong guarantees Ri[x] of the risk functions Ri(x, y) given by (3). This will be done in three steps as follows. First, define
^i(y) = maxfi(z,y) Vy G Y (i G N). Second, construct the Savage-Niehans risk function
Ri (x, y) = Vi (y) — fi (x, y) (i G N). Third, calculate the strong guarantee min [—Ri(x, y)], i.e.,
yeY
Ri[x] = max Ri(x,y) (i G N).
yeY
Note, that the DM seeks to minimize the risk Ri (x, y) with an appropriate alternative x G X under any realization of the uncertainty y G Y.
Whenever the functions fi[x] and —Ri[x] described in the remark exist, they are strong guarantees of fi(x,y) and —Ri (x, y), respectively. Indeed, for each x G X, we have the implications
[fi [x] = min fi (x, y)] ^ [fi [x] < fi (x, y) Vy G Y],
[—Ri[x] = min(-Ri(x,y))] ^ [-Ri[x] < —Rt(x,y) Vy 6 Y].
yeY
The existence of /¿[x] and Rj[x] follows from a well-known result in operation research, which was mentioned earlier.
Lemma 1. (see [23, p.54])
If the sets X and Y are compact and the criteria f (x, y) are continuous on X x Y, then the functions /¿[x] = min /¿(x, y) and ^¿[y] = max /¿(z,y) are continuous on X and Y,
yGY zgX
respectively.
From this point onwards, comp Rn stands for the set of all compact sets from space Rn. In addition, if /¿(x, y) is continuous on X x Y, we will write /¿(x, y) 6 C(X x Y).
Remark 3. If in the MCPU rc the criterion /¿(x,y) 6 C(X x Y), X 6 compRn and Y 6 compRm, then the Savage-Niehans risk function Rj(x,y) (i 6 N) definded by (3) is continuous on X x Y. Indeed, the continuity of ^[y] = max /¿(z, y) follows from Lemma 1, and hence by (3) the function Rj(x, y) = ^>[y] — /¿(x, y) (i 6 N) is also continuous.
Remark 4. The Savage-Niehans risk function (3) characterizes the deviation of the criterion /¿(x, y) from the desired value max /¿(z,y). This stimulates the DM's choice
zgX
of an alternative x 6 X that would reduce as much as possible the difference Rj(x, y) from (3) or, equivalently, maximize —Rj(x,y).
Let us associate with the initial MCPU Tc the 2N-criteria choice problem (4). Once again, at a conceptual level the DM in problem (4) seeks for an alternative x 6 X under which all the 2N criteria /¿(x,y) and —Rj(x,y) (i 6 N) would take the greatest values possible under any realization of the uncertainty y 6 Y.
Formalization of a Guaranteed Solution in Outcomes and Risks
for Problem rc
The MCPUs are well-described in the literature (in particular, we refer to the monograph [24]). The specifics of the interval-type uncertainty y figuring in the problem Tc compel the DM to use in (4) the available information (the limits of the range of values). In this article, our analysis will be confined to the strong guarantees /¿[x] and —Rj[x] of the criteria /¿(x, y) and —Rj(x, y), respectively. Therefore, it seems natural to pass from the MCPU (4) to the multicriteria choice problem of guarantees without uncertainty
rg = (X, {/¿[x], — R*[x]}ieN). The criteria /¿[x] and —Rj[x] in rg are closely related in terms of optimization: the criterion Rj[x] is used for assessing the DM's risk posed by the outcome /¿[x] so that an increase
in the difference fi [x] — Ri [x] leads to a higher guaranteed outcome fi [x] and (or) a lower guaranteed risk Ri[x]. Conversely, a decrease in this difference leads to a lower guaranteed outcome fi[x] and (or) a higher risk Ri[x]. The DM is interested in the maximization of fi [x] with simultaneous minimization of Ri [x] for each i G N. Therefore, we will associate with the original 2N-criteria choice problem rg the auxiliary N-criteria choice problem
ra = (X, {Fi[x] = fi[x] — Ri[x]}i£N). (5)
For a formalization of the optimal solution in guaranteed outcomes and risks for the problem rc, we will use a concept of vector maximum from the theory of multicriteria choice problems [3]. A first optimal solution of this type was introduced in 1909 by Italian economist and sociologist V. Pareto, (1848-1923), and subsequently it because known as Pareto maximum.
The analysis below will employ the concept of Slater maximum, which includes the Pareto maximum as a particular case. Perhaps this concept appeared in the Russian literature after the translation of a paper by Hurwitz [25].
Definition 2. An alternative xS G X is called Slater-maximal (weakly efficient) in the N-criteria choice problem (5) if the system of strict inequalities
Fi[x] >Fi [xS] (i G N)
is inconsistent for any x G X.
Remark 5. By definition 2, an alternative x* G X is not Slater-maximal in problem (5) if there exists an alternative x G X satisfying the N inequalities
Fi [x] >Fi[x*] (i G N).
Proposition 1. If
min ] = maxmin Fjx], (6)
¿eN xgx ¿eN
then the alternative xS G X is Slater-maximal in problem (5).
Доказательство. By equality (6) and Remark 5, for any alternative x G X there exists a number j G N such that [Fj[x] < Fj[xS]] ^ [the system of inequalities Fj [x] > Fj [xS] (i G N) is inconsistent] ^ [xS is Slater-maximal in problem (5)]. □
Theorem 1. If f (■) G C(X x Y) and the sets X and Y are compact, then there exists a Slater-maximal alternative xS G X in problem (5).
Доказательство. Using Lemma 1, we have
[/•(•) e C(X x Y),i e N] ^ [/г[х] e C(X),i e N],
and, in accordance with Remark 3, Rj(-) e C(X x Y)(i e N). Then, again by Lemma 1, min Fj[x] = min(/j[x] — R^x]) e C(X)(i e N). Since the continuous function min F^x]
igN igN igN
definded on the compact set X achieves maximum its at some point xS e X, we arrive at (6), and now the conclusion follows from Proposition 1. □
Definition 3. A triplet (xS, /[xS],R[xS]) is called a strongly-guaranted solution in outcomes and risks (SGOR) of the MCPU Гс if
(1) /i[x] = min/i(x,y),Ri[x] = maxRi(x,y) (i e N);
ygY ygY
(2) the alternative is Slater-maximal in problem (5). Recall that
/[x] = (/![*],..., /n[x]), R[x] = (Rx[x],..., RN[x]),
(7)
Ri[x] = maxRi(x,y), Ri(x,y) = max/i(z,y) — /(x,y)(i e N).
ygY zgX
Why is the strongly-guaranteed solution in outcomes and risks (SGOR) a good solution for the MCPU Гс?
First, it provides an answer to the indigenous Russian question: "What is to be done?". The decision maker is suggested to choose the alternative xS from the triplet (xS,/ [xS ],R[xS ]).
Second, for all i e N, this alternative xS yields outcomes /i(xS, y) that are not smaller than /i[xS] with a risk Ri(xS, y) not exceeding Ri[x] under any realization of the uncertainty y e Y .In other words, xS establishes lower bounds on the outcomes realized under x = xS and also upper bounds on the risks posed by them.
Third, the situation xS implements the largest (Slater-maximal) outcomes and corresponding "minus"risks, i.e., there is no other situation x = xS in which all outcome guarantees /i [xS] would increase and, at the same time, all risk guarantees Ri[xS] would decrease.
In fact, the second and third properties considered together give some analog of the maximin alternative in the single-criterion problem Г under uncertainty if the inner minimum and outer maximum in maximin are replaced by min Fi (x, y)(i e N) and
ygY
Slater maximum, respectively. There are two lines further investigations in this field. In accordance with the first direction, one should substitute Slater maximality with Pareto, Borwein, Geoffrion optimality or conical optimality, and then establish connections between such different solutions. The second direction proceeds from the DM's desire for
higher profits under the lowest guarantees in the sense of Definition 2. Consequently, it is possible to replace scalar minimum (from the inner minimum in maximin) by one of the listed vector minima, thereby increasing the guarantees for some i G N.
Also, it seems interesting to build a bridge between such solutions; some research efforts were made in the monograph [24].
Remark 6. Definition 2 suggests a constructive method of SGOR design. It consists of four steps as follows.
Step 1. Using /¿(x,y), find max /¿(z,y) = ^¿[y] and construct the Savage-Niehans risk
zeX
function Rj(x,y) = ^¿[y] — /¿(x,y) for the criterion /¿(x,y)(i G N).
Step 2. Evaluate the outcome guarantees /¿[x] = min /¿(x,y) and also the risk guarantees
yeY
Rj[x] = max Rj(x,y)(i G N).
yeY
Step 3. For the auxiliary N-criteria choice problem of guarantees ra, calculate the Slater-maximal alternative xS. At this step, we may take advantage of Proposition 2 or perform transition to the concept of Pareto optimality. For the sake of completeness, we recall this concept.
Definition 4. An alternative xP G X is called Pareto-maximal (efficient) in problem (5) if for any alternatives x G X the system of inequalities
Fi[x] > Fi[xP] (i G N), with at least one strict inequality, is inconsistent.
Note that, first, by Definitions 2 and 3, every Pareto-maximal alternative is also Slater-maximal (the converse generally fails); second, by Karlin's lemma [26] , an alternative xP G X that satisfies the condition
max ajFj[x] = ^^ ajFj[xP] (8)
x ¿eN ¿eN
for some a = const > 0 is Pareto-maximal for problem (5).
For the bi-criteria choice problem, letting a1 = a2 = 1 in (8) gives the equality
max (Fi[x] + F2[x]) = Fi[xs] + F2[xs] (9)
xex
for obtaining a Pareto-maximal (hence, Slater-maximal) alternative xS.
Step 4. Using xS, evaluate the guarantees /¿[xS] and Rj[xS](i G N) and compile the two N-dimensional vectors /[xS] = (/1 [xS],..., /N[xS]) and R[xS] = (R1[xS],..., [xS]).
The resulting triplet (xS,/[xS],R[xS]) is the desired SGOR, which complies with Definition 3, i.e., for each criterion /¿(x, y)(i G N) the alternative xS leads to a guaranteed outcome / [xS] with a guaranteed Savage-Niehans risk R [xS].
Risks and Outcomes for Diversification of a Deposit into
Sub-deposits Currencies
As mentioned earlier, in economics all decision makers are divided [26] - [32] into
three categories: risk-averse, risk-neutral and risk-seeking. In this work we will solve the
problem of diversification of a one-year deposit into sub-deposits in national and foreign
currency for a risk-neutral person. Note that a similar problem was addressed in the
paper [1, p.9], and the results established therein differ from those below. The case is that
the Slater solutions generaly form a set of distinct elements. Like in [1], the analysis in
this article involves different elements of the same set.
Let us proceed to the diversification problem. The amount of money in a deposit
diversified into two sub-deposits (in national and foreign currency) accumulated by the
(1 — x)
end of the year can be represented as 0(x, y) = x(1 + r) +--(1 + d)y; see [30, pp.58-
k
60] and also the explanations below. This leads to the single-criterion choice problem r = (X, Y, 0(x,y)), which was studied in [1]. In particular, the guaranteed solutions for risk-averse, risk-neutral and risk-seeking persons was found. In contrast to the paper [1] dealing with the single-criterion choice problem with the criterion 0(x,y), in this work we will consider a bi-criteria analog of the problem r with the criteria
/i(x) = x(1 + r), /2(x,y) = (1—^(1 + d)y. (10)
The first criterion concerns the annual income for the sub-deposit in national currency
from an investment x, while the second concerns the annual income for the sub-deposit in
foreign currency from the residual investment 1 — x. In formula (10), r and d denote the
interest rates for the sub-deposits in national and foreign currency , respectively; k and y
are the exchange rates (to the national value) at the beginning and at the end of the year,
respectively; finally, x 6 [0,1] specifies a proposition in which the main deposit is dedived
into the sub-deposits. Thus, x is the part corresponding to the national sub-deposit,
1x
while the other part 1 — x is converted into foreign currency, —-—, and then allocated to
k
the corresponding sub-deposit. At the end of the year, it is converted back into national (1 — x)
currency, ---(1 + d)y; the resulting amount of money makes up /i(x) + /2(x, y). The
k
decision maker (depositor) has to determine the part x under which the resulting amount of money is as large as possible. It must be taken in account that the future exchange rate y is usually unknown. However, we will assume a range of its possible fluctuations, i.e., y 6 [a, b], where the constants b > a > 0 are given or a priory known.
The mathematical model of the bi-criteria deposit diversification problem can be written as an ordered triplet
r2 = (X = [0,1], Y = [a,b], {/i(x,y)}i=i,2>, (11)
where the functions /¿(x, y) are defined by (10); the set X = [0,1] consists of the DM's alternatives x; Y = [a, b] is the set of uncertainties y; finally, f(x,y) denote the DM's utility function (criteria), and their values are called outcomes. In the terminology of operations research, r2 is a single-criterion choice problem under uncertainty. The DM's desire to take into account the existing uncertain factors has a close connection with risk — "possible deviation of some variables from the desired values". We will use the Savage-Niehans risk function. For problem (5), consider three cases as illustrated at Fig.1, namely,
1 + r
(1) k i+d£
1 + r
(2) k r+d5 *
1 + r (3) a < k-- < b.
v ; 1 + d
1 + r
Рис. 1. The possible arrangements of the point k-- and the interval
1 + d
[a, b] on axis y
Cases 1 and 2. Recall that Г2 is a bi-criteria problem under uncertainty. We will solve it using Definition 4, which is based on the concept of Pareto optimality.
Proposition 2. In cases 1 and 2, the SGOR in the problem Г2 has the explicit form
(xS,/ [xS],R[xS]) = (xS; fi[xS],/2[xS]; Ri[xS^[x5])
1 + d . , , 1 + r
(0; 0, —k—a; 1 + r, 0), if k< a (12)
1 + d 1 + r '
(1; 1 + r, 0; 0, —-—b), if k-- > b.
k 1 + d
That is, in case 1 the DM invests everything in the foreign currency sub-deposit,
obtaining with zero risk a guaranteed minimum amount of —+— a at the end of the
k
year; in case 2, he invests everything in the national currency sub-deposit, obtaining with
zero risk a guaranteed minimum amount of 1 + r at the end of the year. In both cases, the guaranteed minimum amounts are obtained with zero risk under any exchange rate functions y e [a, b] during the year.
Доказательство. We carry out the proof in two steps. In first step, following Remark 6, we construct the resulting 2N-criteria choice problem of guarantees rg and then the N-criteria choice problem (5). In the second step, for this problem (5), we find the Slater-maximal alternative xS using Proposition 1 and then calculate the explicit form of the SGOR for the bi-criteria choice problem (5). First step. In (5), the criteria are given by
(1 x)
/i(x, y) = /i(x) = x(1 + r), /2(x, y) = —-^(1 + d)y. Sub-step 1. Using (3), construct the Savage-Niehans risk function
R1(x,y) = [max /1 (z)] — (1 + r)x = (1 + r) — x(1 + r) = (1 — x)(1 + r),
zg [0,1]
, , r . ^ . ч 1 + d 1 + d (Л x 1 +d
R2(x,y) = [max /2(z)] — (1 — x)^— y = —T-y — (1 — x)^— y = xy—T-.
zg[0,1] k k k k
Sub-step 2. Now, calculate the strong guarantees in outcomes and risks
/1 [x] = min x(1 + r) = x(1 + r) , yg [a,b]
/2[x] = min (1 — x)—+— y = (1 — x)—+— a,
yg [a,b] k k
R1[x] = max R1(x, y) = (1 — x)(1 + r), yg [a,b]
1+d
R2[x] = max R2(x,y) = x—-—b.
yg [a,b] k
Sub-step 3. The quad-criteria choice problem of guarantees takes the form
rg = (X = [0,1], {/i[x], —Ri[x]}i=i,2). Step 2 also allows us to define the criteria
F1[x] = /1 [x] — R1[x] = x(1 + r) — (1 — x)(1 + r) = (2x — 1)(1 + r),
1 + d 1 + d 1 + d 1 + d F2 [x] = /2 [x] — R2 [x] = (1 — x)—k—a — x——b = —k—a--— (a + b)x
in the auxiliary bi-criteria problem (5)
ra = (X = [0,1], {Fi[x]}i=i,2>.
where
Second step. Sub-step 4. Maximize the sum of criteria
max (Fi [x] + F2[x]) = FJx5] + F2[xS]. [0,1]
The resulting Pareto-maximal (ergo, Slater-maximal) alternative xS is
F [xS ] = max F [x], (13)
[0,1]
F[x] = F1[x]+ F2[x] = (2x - 1)(1 + r) + 1a - 1(a + b)x
kk
= x[2(1 + r) - 1(a + b)] - (1 + r) + 1a kk
= 1{[27 - (a + b)]x - y + a},
1 + r
and y = ^ ^k. The function F[x] under maximization is linear in x and defined on the interval [0,1]. Therefore, it achieves maximum at one of the endpoints of this interval,
i.e., either at x = 0, or at x = 1. For x = 0, we have F[0] = —+— (a - y); for x = 1,
k
1+d
F[1] = — (Y - b).
Lemma 2. The next implication is valid
[a > Y] ^ [F[0] > F[1]].
Доказательство. Indeed
г , гг a + a 1 ra + b ,i г ,,
[a > Y] ^ [-— > Y] ^ [-— > Y] ^ [a - Y > Y - b]
^ [F[0] = 1(a - y) > F[1] = 1(y - b)]'
□
In a similar fashion, we can easily establish Lemma 3. The implication
[Y > b] ^ [F[0] < F[1]]
is valid.
Доказательство. Indeed,
г г г b + b, г b + a i r , i
[y > b] ^ [y > ^ [y > ^H ^ [y - b > a - y]
^ [F[1] = 1(y — b) > F[0] = 1(a — y)].
□
By lemmas 2 and 3 , the maximum in (13) is achieved
(a) at xS = 0 if a > y;
(b) at xS = 1 if y > b.
The corresponding guarantees are calculated using this result and Sub-step 2:
/1[0] = 0,/2[0] = 1-+da,R1[0] = 1 + r R2 [0] = 0; /1[1] = 1 + r, /2 [0] = 0, R1 [0] = 1, R2 [0] = 1-+db.
1 + r
Recall that y = -;k, and the proof of Proposition 2 is complete. □
1+d
Let us make a few of remarks. First, R1[0] = 1 + r (the Savage-Niehans risk). The
value R2[0] = —+— b has a similar meaning. Second, Proposition 2 was proved in the k
paper [29] using a different technique.
Finally, consider case 3. Here we will utilize, first, the results of Sub-step 3 of Proposition 2, in particular, the bi-criteria choice problem
ra = (X = [0,1], (Fi[x]}i=1,2),
where
F1[x] = (2x — 1)(1 + r),
„ г 1 1 + d 1 + d. ,, (14)
F 2 [x] = —k—a--— (a + b)x;
second, the sufficient conditions (6) for the existence of the alternative xS (see Proposition 1), writing them for the deposit diversification problem (5) as
min Fi [xS] = max min Fi [x].
i—1,2 xg[0,1] i=1,2
1+r
Proposition 3. If a < --k < b, the SGOR in the problem Г2 has the form
1+d
(xS,/[xS],R[xS]) = (xS; /1[xS], /2[xS]; R1[xS],R2[xS])
= f Y + a ; (y + a)(1 + r) Y + b 1 + d ; = V2y + a + b; 2y + a + b , 2y + a + b k a; (15)
(1 + r) Y + b ,,b1P- Y + a ,).
v 2y + a + b k 2y + a + b)
Доказательство. Draw the graphs of the two functions F1[x] and F2[x] from (14). These functions are linear in x and defined on the interval [0,1] (a compact set); see Fig.2.
In Fig. 2 the function min {F\[x], F2[x]} is indicated by the bold line, see the angle
¿=1,2
ABC. For max min {F1[x], F2[x]}, the point B satisfies the equality xe[0,i] ¿=1,2
F1[xS ] = F2[xS ]
or, using (14)
x
1 + d . 2(1 + r) +--— (a + b)
1 + r
1+d = 1 + r +---— a.
With the notation y =--k, it can be written as
1+d
xS [2y + a + b] = y + a,
which gives
xS = _ Y + a 1 - xS = Y + b
2y + a + b
2y + a + b
Using the formulas of Sub-step 2, we calculate the strong guarantees in outcomes and risks:
/i[xS ] = (1 + r) R1[xS ] = (1 + r)
Y + a
2y + a + b'
Y + b 2y + a + b
/2 [xS ] =
1 + d y + b
R2[xS ] = —— b
k 2y + a + b'
1 + d y + a
k 2y + a + b
□
1 + r
Thus, we have established the following result (see Proposition 3). If a < ^ ^k < b, the strongly-guaranteed solution in outcomes and risks of the deposit diversification
problem has form (15). It suggests the DM to invest the part —Y-^ in the national
2y + a + b
Y + b
currency sub-deposit and the residual part-- in the foreign currency sub-deposit.
2y + a + b
At the end of the year, the DM will obtain the amount (1 + r)—Y-^ for the national
* ' V 2y + a + b
Y + b
currency sub-deposit with the Savage-Niehans risk (1 + r)-- and the amount
2y + a + b
—+— a(1 + r) ^ Y+ ^ ^ (after conversion in national currency) for the foreign currency
sub-deposit with the Savage-Niehans risk —+— b—Y+- under the exchange rate
k 2y + a + b
fluctuations y 6 [a, b] during the year.
Puc. 2. Graphs of functions defined by (14).
1+r
Remark 7. If ^ ^ k < a (case 1), the DM is recommended to invest everything in the foreign currency sub-deposit, because at the end of the year he will obtain the guaranteed
minimum income —+— a with zero risk (Proposition 2). k
1+r
If ^ ^k > b (case 2), the DM is recommended to invest everything in the national currency sub-deposit, which will yield him the guaranteed minimum income (1 + r) with
zero risk at the end of the year (Proposition 2).
список литературы
1. Капитоненко, В. В. Финансовая математика и ее приложения. — M.: ПРИОР, 2000. — 42 с.
KAPITONENKO, V. V. (2000) Financial Mathematics and Its Applications. Moscow: Prior.
2. Колемаев, В. А. Математическая экономика. — M.: ЮНИТИ, 2002. — 53 с. KOLEMAEV, V. A. (2002) Mathematical Economics. Moscow: Yuniti.
3. SAVAGE, L. Y. (1954) The Foundation of Statistics. New York: Wiley.
4. SAVAGE, L. Y. (1951) The theory of Statistical Decision. J. American Statistic Assosiation. 46. p. 55-67.
5. NICANS, J. (1951) Zur Preisbildung bei Unterwissen. Zchweizerische Zeitschrift Association. 46 (3). p. 55-67.
6. Гермейер, Ю. Б. Введение в исследование операций. — M.: Наука, 1971. — 34 c. GERMEIER, Y. B. (1971) Introduction to Operation Research. Moscow: Nauka.
7. Гермейер, Ю. Б. Игры с непротивоположными интересами. — M.: Наука, 1976. — 64 c.
GERMEIER, Y. B. (1976) Games with Nonopposite Interests. Moscow: Nauka.
8. Мушик, Э., Мюллер, П. Методы принятия технических решений. — M.: Мир, 1990. — 56 c.
MUSCHICK, E. and MULLER, P. (1990) Methods of Technical Decision-Making. Moscow: Mir.
9. Найт, Ф. Х. Риск, неопределенность и прибыль. — M.: Дело, 2003. — 86 c. KNIGHT, F. H. (2003) Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Moscow: Delo.
10. Жуковский, В. И. Конфликты и риски. — M.: ЗосЗИТЛП, 2007. — 54 c.
ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I. (2007) Conflicts and Risks. Moscow: Ross. Zaochn. Inst. Tekstil. Legk. Promysh.
11. Жуковский, В. И.. Риски при конфликтных ситуациях. — M.: УРСС, ЛЕНАНД, 2011. — 78 c.
ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I. (2011) Risks in Conflict Situations. Moscow: URSS.
12. Жуковский, В. И., Жуковская, Л. В. Риски в многокритериальных и конфликтных системах при неопределенности. — M.: Эдиториал УРСС, 2004. — 67 с.
ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I., ZHUKOVSKAYA, L. V. (2004) Risks in Multicriteria Choice and Conflict Systems under Uncertainty. Moscow: URSS.
13. WALD, A. (1939) Contribution to the Theory of Statistical Estimation and Testing Hypothesis. Annuals Math. Statist.. 10. p. 299-326.
14. WALD, A. (1950) A Statistical Decision Functions. N.Y.: Wiley.
15. Ауман, Р. Дж. Эеономический индекс рискованности // Российский журнал менеджмента. — 2007. — Т. 5. — C. 3-14.
AUMANN, R. (2007) An Economic Index of Riskiness. Russian Management Journal. 5 (5). p. 3-14.
16. Черкасов, В. В.. Проблемы риска в управленческой деятельности. — M.: Рефл-бук, 1999. — 78 c.
CHERKASOV, V. V. (1999) Risk Problems in Management. Moscow: Refa-buk.
17. Шахов, В. В.. Введение в страхование. Экономический аспект. — M.: Финансы и статистика, 1994. — 52 c.
SHAKHOV, V. V. (1994) Introduction to Insurance. Economic Aspect. Moscow: Finansi i Statistika.
18. Черемных, Ю. Н.. Микроэкономика. Продвинутый уровень. — M.: Инфо-М, 2008. — 60 c.
CHEREMNYKH, Y. N. (2008) Microeconomics: Advance Level. Moscow: Info-M.
19. Цветкова, Е. В., Арлюкова, И. О. Риски в экономической деятельности. — Санкт-Петербург: СПбИВЭСЭП, 2002. — 76 c.
TSVETKOVA, E. V. and ARLYUKOVA, I. O. (2002) Risks in Economic Activity. St.-Peterburg: Inst. Vneshneekon. Svyav. Ekon. Prav.
20. MARKOVITS, H. M. (1952) Portfolio Selection. Journal of Finance. 7 (1). p. 77-89.
21. Жуковский, В. И., Кудрявцев, К. Н. Уравновешивание конфликтов при неопределенности. I. Аналог седловой точки // Математическая Теория Игр и ее Приложения. — 2013. — Т. 5. — C. 27-44.
ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I. and KUDRYAVTSEV, K. N. (2013) Equilibrating Conflicts under Uncertainty. I. Analog of a Saddle-Point. Mat. Teor. Igr Prilozh.. 5 (1). p. 27-44.
22. Жуковский, В. И., Кудрявцев, К. Н. Уравновешивание конфликтов при неопределенности. II. Аналог максимина // Математическая Теория Игр и ее Приложения. - 2013. - Т. 5. - C. 3-45.
ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I. and KUDRYAVTSEV, K. N. (2013) Equilibrating Conflicts under Uncertainty. II. Analog of a Maximin. Mat. Teor. Igr Prilozh.. 5 (2). p. 3-45.
23. Дмитрук, А. В. Выпуклый анализ. Элементарный вводный курс. — M.: МАКС-ПРЕСС, 2012. - 34 c.
DMITRUK, A. V (2012) Convex analysis. Elementary introductory course. Moscow: MAKS-PRESS.
24. ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I., SALUKVADZE, M. E. (1994) The vector-valued maximin. N.Y. etc: Academic Press.
25. ARROW, K. J., HURWICZ, L. and UZAWA, H. (1958) Studies in Linear and Nonlinear Programming. Stanford Mathematical Studies in the Social Sciences, Stanford Univ. Press.
26. KARLIN, S. (1959) Mathematical Methods and Theory in Games. Programming and Economics, London-Paris: Pergamon Press.
27. Клейманов, А. Ф. Неантогонистические позиционные дифференциальные игры. - М.: Наука, 1993. - 86 c.
KLEIMENOV, A. F. (1993) Nonantogonistic Positional Differential Games. Yekaterinburg: Nauka.
28. Колесник, Г. В. Теория игр. - М.: СПбИВЭСЭП, 2010. - 120 c. KOLESNIK, G. V. (2010) Game Theory. Moscow: Либроком.
29. Кудрявцев, К. Н., Стабулит, И. С. Гарантированное по Парето равновесие в дуополии Хотеллинга на плоскости // Вестник Южно-Уральского государственного университета. Серия: Математическое моделирование и программирование. - 2012. - Т. 14. - C. 173-177.
KUDRYAVTSEV, K. N. and STABULIT, I. S. (2012) Pareto-Guaranteed Equilibrium in 2D Hotelling Duopoly. Vest. Yuzhno-Ural. Gos. Univ. Ser. Mat. Modelir. Programmir.. 14 (40). p. 173-177.
30. Жуковский, В. И., Чикрий, А. А., Солдатова, Н. Г. Равновесие по Бержу в конфликтах при неопределенности // Сборник 12 Всероссийского совещания по проблемам управления. — М.: Институт управления им. В.А. Трапезникова РАН, 2014. - C. 8290-8302.
ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I., CHIKRII, A. A. and SOLDATOVA, N. G. (2014) The Berge Equilibrium in the Conflicts under Uncertainty. Proc. XII All-Russian Meeting on Control Problems (AMCP-114), Moscow: Inst. Probl. Upravlen..8290-8302
31. ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I., SALUKVADZE, M. E. (2020) The Berge Equilibrium: A Game-Theoretic Framework for Golden Rule of Ethics. Springer.
32. ZHUKOVSKIY, V. I., SALUKVADZE, M. E. (2021) The Berge Equilibrium: A Game-Theoretic Framework for Golden Rule of Ethics. A Dynamic-Theoretic Framework Based of Berge Equilibrium. N.Y.: CRC Press Taylor and Francis Group.